User login
The Right Choice? A New Chapter
As I write this last installment of “The Right Choice?” for ACS Surgery News, a number of different emotions are going through my mind all at the same time. I am surprised at how quickly the time has passed since I wrote my first surgical ethics column for SN in 2011. In the 33 columns that I have written since then, I have tried to focus on aspects of surgical practice that emphasize the ethical dimension. I have tried to write columns that would be of interest to practicing surgeons in any setting and not only to academic surgeons that practice in urban environments such as I practice in. This is the last column and thus the end of a chapter of my life and the beginning of a new one.
Over the last 7 years, I have been flattered by the comments from fellow surgeons who report that they actually read the column. I have always said that I wrote this column with the expectation that no one would actually read them. I have to confess that this is not completely true. As I wrote each column, I did so as though I was writing them for my father to read. My father, S. Peter Angelos, MD, FACS, was a general surgeon who spent his entire career practicing in the town of Plattsburgh, N.Y., where he grew up. My father’s practice was very different from mine. I work at an urban academic medical center where I have a very narrow subspecialty practice in endocrine surgery. My father had a small-town community practice of “bread and butter” general surgery. Yet, when he and I would talk about patients, the commonality of the relationship between a surgeon and a patient transcended these differences. I realize that in many ways, I wrote this column as a way of organizing my own thoughts and then presenting them to my father in the hopes that he would find them of some value.
For several years, I would send drafts of my column to my parents, and both my father and mother would read them and give me suggestions. Many of the earlier columns were changed for the better by their comments. In recent years, my father’s health declined and he was no longer able to give me comments. Nevertheless, I continued to compose them as though writing for him. Approximately 6 weeks ago, my father passed away. It has been sad for my mother and my entire family. We all realized that it was the end of one chapter of our lives and the start of a new one without my father.
I find the concept of “beginning a new chapter” to be an important one for surgeons to reflect upon. There are certain events, such as the death of a parent, that force us to think about the end of one phase of life and the beginning of another phase. However, the division of one’s experience into phases or chapters, is somewhat arbitrary. This past summer I became a patient and had surgery myself for the first time. I cannot help but think of that operation as the start of a new chapter for me. I am convinced that although all patients may not reflect upon surgery in the same way that I did, nevertheless, an operation is a dramatic event that most people remember for a long time. In this context, many people will see their interactions with their surgeon and their operation as the end of one chapter and the beginning of a new one.
In this context, it is critical for surgeons to be fully cognizant of the great impact that we may have on our patient’s internal narratives of their lives. When we operate on someone, we run the risk of that person’s functional status changing forever. We may be the means by which our patient is cured of cancer or suffers a debilitating complication. As surgeons, we therefore, occupy a potentially significant role in the trajectory of our patients’ lives. I believe that the relationship between a surgeon and a patient is distinctive and central in the narrative that so many patients create about their lives. It is essential that surgeons continue to appreciate the value of the quality of that relationship with our patients and the impact—potentially positive or negative—that it can have upon our patients.
Throughout medicine, in general, and in surgery in particular, one cannot go a week without hearing about the problem of burnout. Although there is no single cure for burnout, I do believe that paying attention to the ethical dimension of our interactions with our patients and the impact that surgery can have on their lives will go a long way to reducing the risks of burnout among surgeons.
In an era in which we are often pushed to increase RVUs at the expense of spending time with individual patients, we must not forget how significant our relationships with our patients can be. I believe that attention to this relationship will be beneficial to patients and also to us as we help our patients start new chapters in their lives.
Dr. Angelos is the Linda Kohler Anderson Professor of Surgery and Surgical Ethics, chief of endocrine surgery, and associate director of the MacLean Center for Clinical Medical Ethics at the University of Chicago.
As I write this last installment of “The Right Choice?” for ACS Surgery News, a number of different emotions are going through my mind all at the same time. I am surprised at how quickly the time has passed since I wrote my first surgical ethics column for SN in 2011. In the 33 columns that I have written since then, I have tried to focus on aspects of surgical practice that emphasize the ethical dimension. I have tried to write columns that would be of interest to practicing surgeons in any setting and not only to academic surgeons that practice in urban environments such as I practice in. This is the last column and thus the end of a chapter of my life and the beginning of a new one.
Over the last 7 years, I have been flattered by the comments from fellow surgeons who report that they actually read the column. I have always said that I wrote this column with the expectation that no one would actually read them. I have to confess that this is not completely true. As I wrote each column, I did so as though I was writing them for my father to read. My father, S. Peter Angelos, MD, FACS, was a general surgeon who spent his entire career practicing in the town of Plattsburgh, N.Y., where he grew up. My father’s practice was very different from mine. I work at an urban academic medical center where I have a very narrow subspecialty practice in endocrine surgery. My father had a small-town community practice of “bread and butter” general surgery. Yet, when he and I would talk about patients, the commonality of the relationship between a surgeon and a patient transcended these differences. I realize that in many ways, I wrote this column as a way of organizing my own thoughts and then presenting them to my father in the hopes that he would find them of some value.
For several years, I would send drafts of my column to my parents, and both my father and mother would read them and give me suggestions. Many of the earlier columns were changed for the better by their comments. In recent years, my father’s health declined and he was no longer able to give me comments. Nevertheless, I continued to compose them as though writing for him. Approximately 6 weeks ago, my father passed away. It has been sad for my mother and my entire family. We all realized that it was the end of one chapter of our lives and the start of a new one without my father.
I find the concept of “beginning a new chapter” to be an important one for surgeons to reflect upon. There are certain events, such as the death of a parent, that force us to think about the end of one phase of life and the beginning of another phase. However, the division of one’s experience into phases or chapters, is somewhat arbitrary. This past summer I became a patient and had surgery myself for the first time. I cannot help but think of that operation as the start of a new chapter for me. I am convinced that although all patients may not reflect upon surgery in the same way that I did, nevertheless, an operation is a dramatic event that most people remember for a long time. In this context, many people will see their interactions with their surgeon and their operation as the end of one chapter and the beginning of a new one.
In this context, it is critical for surgeons to be fully cognizant of the great impact that we may have on our patient’s internal narratives of their lives. When we operate on someone, we run the risk of that person’s functional status changing forever. We may be the means by which our patient is cured of cancer or suffers a debilitating complication. As surgeons, we therefore, occupy a potentially significant role in the trajectory of our patients’ lives. I believe that the relationship between a surgeon and a patient is distinctive and central in the narrative that so many patients create about their lives. It is essential that surgeons continue to appreciate the value of the quality of that relationship with our patients and the impact—potentially positive or negative—that it can have upon our patients.
Throughout medicine, in general, and in surgery in particular, one cannot go a week without hearing about the problem of burnout. Although there is no single cure for burnout, I do believe that paying attention to the ethical dimension of our interactions with our patients and the impact that surgery can have on their lives will go a long way to reducing the risks of burnout among surgeons.
In an era in which we are often pushed to increase RVUs at the expense of spending time with individual patients, we must not forget how significant our relationships with our patients can be. I believe that attention to this relationship will be beneficial to patients and also to us as we help our patients start new chapters in their lives.
Dr. Angelos is the Linda Kohler Anderson Professor of Surgery and Surgical Ethics, chief of endocrine surgery, and associate director of the MacLean Center for Clinical Medical Ethics at the University of Chicago.
As I write this last installment of “The Right Choice?” for ACS Surgery News, a number of different emotions are going through my mind all at the same time. I am surprised at how quickly the time has passed since I wrote my first surgical ethics column for SN in 2011. In the 33 columns that I have written since then, I have tried to focus on aspects of surgical practice that emphasize the ethical dimension. I have tried to write columns that would be of interest to practicing surgeons in any setting and not only to academic surgeons that practice in urban environments such as I practice in. This is the last column and thus the end of a chapter of my life and the beginning of a new one.
Over the last 7 years, I have been flattered by the comments from fellow surgeons who report that they actually read the column. I have always said that I wrote this column with the expectation that no one would actually read them. I have to confess that this is not completely true. As I wrote each column, I did so as though I was writing them for my father to read. My father, S. Peter Angelos, MD, FACS, was a general surgeon who spent his entire career practicing in the town of Plattsburgh, N.Y., where he grew up. My father’s practice was very different from mine. I work at an urban academic medical center where I have a very narrow subspecialty practice in endocrine surgery. My father had a small-town community practice of “bread and butter” general surgery. Yet, when he and I would talk about patients, the commonality of the relationship between a surgeon and a patient transcended these differences. I realize that in many ways, I wrote this column as a way of organizing my own thoughts and then presenting them to my father in the hopes that he would find them of some value.
For several years, I would send drafts of my column to my parents, and both my father and mother would read them and give me suggestions. Many of the earlier columns were changed for the better by their comments. In recent years, my father’s health declined and he was no longer able to give me comments. Nevertheless, I continued to compose them as though writing for him. Approximately 6 weeks ago, my father passed away. It has been sad for my mother and my entire family. We all realized that it was the end of one chapter of our lives and the start of a new one without my father.
I find the concept of “beginning a new chapter” to be an important one for surgeons to reflect upon. There are certain events, such as the death of a parent, that force us to think about the end of one phase of life and the beginning of another phase. However, the division of one’s experience into phases or chapters, is somewhat arbitrary. This past summer I became a patient and had surgery myself for the first time. I cannot help but think of that operation as the start of a new chapter for me. I am convinced that although all patients may not reflect upon surgery in the same way that I did, nevertheless, an operation is a dramatic event that most people remember for a long time. In this context, many people will see their interactions with their surgeon and their operation as the end of one chapter and the beginning of a new one.
In this context, it is critical for surgeons to be fully cognizant of the great impact that we may have on our patient’s internal narratives of their lives. When we operate on someone, we run the risk of that person’s functional status changing forever. We may be the means by which our patient is cured of cancer or suffers a debilitating complication. As surgeons, we therefore, occupy a potentially significant role in the trajectory of our patients’ lives. I believe that the relationship between a surgeon and a patient is distinctive and central in the narrative that so many patients create about their lives. It is essential that surgeons continue to appreciate the value of the quality of that relationship with our patients and the impact—potentially positive or negative—that it can have upon our patients.
Throughout medicine, in general, and in surgery in particular, one cannot go a week without hearing about the problem of burnout. Although there is no single cure for burnout, I do believe that paying attention to the ethical dimension of our interactions with our patients and the impact that surgery can have on their lives will go a long way to reducing the risks of burnout among surgeons.
In an era in which we are often pushed to increase RVUs at the expense of spending time with individual patients, we must not forget how significant our relationships with our patients can be. I believe that attention to this relationship will be beneficial to patients and also to us as we help our patients start new chapters in their lives.
Dr. Angelos is the Linda Kohler Anderson Professor of Surgery and Surgical Ethics, chief of endocrine surgery, and associate director of the MacLean Center for Clinical Medical Ethics at the University of Chicago.
Communication and consent
We knew that the case would be a difficult one. The patient was a man in his mid-40s who had several serious chronic conditions and was on high-dose steroids. He had been operated on 10 days earlier by one of my partners for a bowel obstruction and had required a resection of a small portion of the terminal ileum. Unfortunately, on the day after surgery, it became obvious that the patient needed a reexploration for bleeding. He had developed clear evidence of a significant anastomotic leak and had to be taken emergently back to the operating room.
His condition had been worsening during the day. We had booked the case in the OR but had been put off by a trauma emergency and a neurosurgical emergency. During the 3 hours of waiting to take him to the OR, the patient’s sister and mother came to the hospital and were now waiting with him in the preop area. I was on my way up to see him when my resident called. Despite the patient having signed an operative consent form a few hours earlier when we booked the case, he was now “declining” an operation. I was surprised. This man had undergone several operations in the last few years and two in the last 2 weeks. I arrived to find the patient stating that he did not want surgery. Lying in bed, he was adamant that he should not have surgery. The surgical resident who had spoken with the patient several times over the last few hours was also surprised. The patient’s family members were yelling that, of course, he wanted surgery and why would he change his mind.
This is a difficult situation since one of the central tenets of the ethical practice of surgery is to allow patients to make decisions about their own care. The right to make autonomous choices even extends to circumstances in which patients make what we might consider “bad” decisions. As long as the patient has the capacity to make an autonomous choice, he or she should have that choice respected.
This patient, who just a few hours ago had agreed to surgery, now seemed to have changed his mind. Although it can be frustrating, we do allow patients to change their minds. On the one hand, this was a straightforward case. The patient was refusing a potentially life-saving operation. Such a situation is never pleasant for a surgeon, but as long as the patient understands the risks, we respect such choices.
However, my resident made an astute observation. She pointed out that, when asked why he now did not want surgery, he replied that “this is all a movie – it’s not really happening.” The patient appeared to be oriented to person and place, but nevertheless, his reasoning seemed to have been altered. It appeared that this patient was no longer making sense because his underlying medical condition had deteriorated. We considered whether he was becoming septic and that this change in medical condition had rendered him unable to make an informed decision. My resident, who had discussed the operation with the patient several times, stated that the patient’s decision making seemed very different than even an hour ago. His family members agreed, stating that, up until a few minutes before, he was in favor of surgery. They pleaded with us to just take him into the operating room.
We considered our options. We could delay surgery and consult psychiatry to ask them to assess his competency. However, on a weekend night, this would likely take several hours. We considered the option of waiting in the preop area for the patient’s medical condition to further worsen. If he became overtly septic and lost consciousness, then we could readily turn to the family members – his surrogate decision makers – and ask them to consent to the procedure. Although this “by the book” approach might take away any worry that we were overriding an autonomous patient’s choice, we knew that it would unnecessarily expose him to greater operative risks. This option was not in his best interest and therefore not much of an option.
Ultimately, the surgical resident, the attending anesthesiologist, the family, and I decided that his decision to not have surgery at this moment was not consistent with his prior decisions, and he could provide no reason for changing his mind. We brought the patient into the operating room and explored him. He did have a large anastomotic leak with a large volume of enteric contents in the peritoneal cavity. He survived the operation and, not unexpectedly, required a long postoperative stay in the hospital. Once he was a few days out, I inquired about whether he was glad that he had surgery. He was quick to state his confidence that it had been the right choice for him. He did not even remember having ever refused the surgery.
Although this case raised many concerns for all of us involved in the patient’s care, one overriding lesson that came through to me. Informed consent should not be viewed as a solitary event, but a conversation. This patient had expressed his desire to have surgery multiple times to my surgical resident and to his family. Even though we should never take the position that patients cannot change their minds, we should carefully question those choices that are inconsistent with the prior discussions that have been undertaken. Good communication skills – including listening to the patient, understanding the patient’s reasoning, and reflecting on the entire conversation – are essential in obtaining informed consent.
Dr. Angelos is the Linda Kohler Anderson Professor of Surgery and Surgical Ethics, chief of endocrine surgery, and associate director of the MacLean Center for Clinical Medical Ethics at the University of Chicago.
We knew that the case would be a difficult one. The patient was a man in his mid-40s who had several serious chronic conditions and was on high-dose steroids. He had been operated on 10 days earlier by one of my partners for a bowel obstruction and had required a resection of a small portion of the terminal ileum. Unfortunately, on the day after surgery, it became obvious that the patient needed a reexploration for bleeding. He had developed clear evidence of a significant anastomotic leak and had to be taken emergently back to the operating room.
His condition had been worsening during the day. We had booked the case in the OR but had been put off by a trauma emergency and a neurosurgical emergency. During the 3 hours of waiting to take him to the OR, the patient’s sister and mother came to the hospital and were now waiting with him in the preop area. I was on my way up to see him when my resident called. Despite the patient having signed an operative consent form a few hours earlier when we booked the case, he was now “declining” an operation. I was surprised. This man had undergone several operations in the last few years and two in the last 2 weeks. I arrived to find the patient stating that he did not want surgery. Lying in bed, he was adamant that he should not have surgery. The surgical resident who had spoken with the patient several times over the last few hours was also surprised. The patient’s family members were yelling that, of course, he wanted surgery and why would he change his mind.
This is a difficult situation since one of the central tenets of the ethical practice of surgery is to allow patients to make decisions about their own care. The right to make autonomous choices even extends to circumstances in which patients make what we might consider “bad” decisions. As long as the patient has the capacity to make an autonomous choice, he or she should have that choice respected.
This patient, who just a few hours ago had agreed to surgery, now seemed to have changed his mind. Although it can be frustrating, we do allow patients to change their minds. On the one hand, this was a straightforward case. The patient was refusing a potentially life-saving operation. Such a situation is never pleasant for a surgeon, but as long as the patient understands the risks, we respect such choices.
However, my resident made an astute observation. She pointed out that, when asked why he now did not want surgery, he replied that “this is all a movie – it’s not really happening.” The patient appeared to be oriented to person and place, but nevertheless, his reasoning seemed to have been altered. It appeared that this patient was no longer making sense because his underlying medical condition had deteriorated. We considered whether he was becoming septic and that this change in medical condition had rendered him unable to make an informed decision. My resident, who had discussed the operation with the patient several times, stated that the patient’s decision making seemed very different than even an hour ago. His family members agreed, stating that, up until a few minutes before, he was in favor of surgery. They pleaded with us to just take him into the operating room.
We considered our options. We could delay surgery and consult psychiatry to ask them to assess his competency. However, on a weekend night, this would likely take several hours. We considered the option of waiting in the preop area for the patient’s medical condition to further worsen. If he became overtly septic and lost consciousness, then we could readily turn to the family members – his surrogate decision makers – and ask them to consent to the procedure. Although this “by the book” approach might take away any worry that we were overriding an autonomous patient’s choice, we knew that it would unnecessarily expose him to greater operative risks. This option was not in his best interest and therefore not much of an option.
Ultimately, the surgical resident, the attending anesthesiologist, the family, and I decided that his decision to not have surgery at this moment was not consistent with his prior decisions, and he could provide no reason for changing his mind. We brought the patient into the operating room and explored him. He did have a large anastomotic leak with a large volume of enteric contents in the peritoneal cavity. He survived the operation and, not unexpectedly, required a long postoperative stay in the hospital. Once he was a few days out, I inquired about whether he was glad that he had surgery. He was quick to state his confidence that it had been the right choice for him. He did not even remember having ever refused the surgery.
Although this case raised many concerns for all of us involved in the patient’s care, one overriding lesson that came through to me. Informed consent should not be viewed as a solitary event, but a conversation. This patient had expressed his desire to have surgery multiple times to my surgical resident and to his family. Even though we should never take the position that patients cannot change their minds, we should carefully question those choices that are inconsistent with the prior discussions that have been undertaken. Good communication skills – including listening to the patient, understanding the patient’s reasoning, and reflecting on the entire conversation – are essential in obtaining informed consent.
Dr. Angelos is the Linda Kohler Anderson Professor of Surgery and Surgical Ethics, chief of endocrine surgery, and associate director of the MacLean Center for Clinical Medical Ethics at the University of Chicago.
We knew that the case would be a difficult one. The patient was a man in his mid-40s who had several serious chronic conditions and was on high-dose steroids. He had been operated on 10 days earlier by one of my partners for a bowel obstruction and had required a resection of a small portion of the terminal ileum. Unfortunately, on the day after surgery, it became obvious that the patient needed a reexploration for bleeding. He had developed clear evidence of a significant anastomotic leak and had to be taken emergently back to the operating room.
His condition had been worsening during the day. We had booked the case in the OR but had been put off by a trauma emergency and a neurosurgical emergency. During the 3 hours of waiting to take him to the OR, the patient’s sister and mother came to the hospital and were now waiting with him in the preop area. I was on my way up to see him when my resident called. Despite the patient having signed an operative consent form a few hours earlier when we booked the case, he was now “declining” an operation. I was surprised. This man had undergone several operations in the last few years and two in the last 2 weeks. I arrived to find the patient stating that he did not want surgery. Lying in bed, he was adamant that he should not have surgery. The surgical resident who had spoken with the patient several times over the last few hours was also surprised. The patient’s family members were yelling that, of course, he wanted surgery and why would he change his mind.
This is a difficult situation since one of the central tenets of the ethical practice of surgery is to allow patients to make decisions about their own care. The right to make autonomous choices even extends to circumstances in which patients make what we might consider “bad” decisions. As long as the patient has the capacity to make an autonomous choice, he or she should have that choice respected.
This patient, who just a few hours ago had agreed to surgery, now seemed to have changed his mind. Although it can be frustrating, we do allow patients to change their minds. On the one hand, this was a straightforward case. The patient was refusing a potentially life-saving operation. Such a situation is never pleasant for a surgeon, but as long as the patient understands the risks, we respect such choices.
However, my resident made an astute observation. She pointed out that, when asked why he now did not want surgery, he replied that “this is all a movie – it’s not really happening.” The patient appeared to be oriented to person and place, but nevertheless, his reasoning seemed to have been altered. It appeared that this patient was no longer making sense because his underlying medical condition had deteriorated. We considered whether he was becoming septic and that this change in medical condition had rendered him unable to make an informed decision. My resident, who had discussed the operation with the patient several times, stated that the patient’s decision making seemed very different than even an hour ago. His family members agreed, stating that, up until a few minutes before, he was in favor of surgery. They pleaded with us to just take him into the operating room.
We considered our options. We could delay surgery and consult psychiatry to ask them to assess his competency. However, on a weekend night, this would likely take several hours. We considered the option of waiting in the preop area for the patient’s medical condition to further worsen. If he became overtly septic and lost consciousness, then we could readily turn to the family members – his surrogate decision makers – and ask them to consent to the procedure. Although this “by the book” approach might take away any worry that we were overriding an autonomous patient’s choice, we knew that it would unnecessarily expose him to greater operative risks. This option was not in his best interest and therefore not much of an option.
Ultimately, the surgical resident, the attending anesthesiologist, the family, and I decided that his decision to not have surgery at this moment was not consistent with his prior decisions, and he could provide no reason for changing his mind. We brought the patient into the operating room and explored him. He did have a large anastomotic leak with a large volume of enteric contents in the peritoneal cavity. He survived the operation and, not unexpectedly, required a long postoperative stay in the hospital. Once he was a few days out, I inquired about whether he was glad that he had surgery. He was quick to state his confidence that it had been the right choice for him. He did not even remember having ever refused the surgery.
Although this case raised many concerns for all of us involved in the patient’s care, one overriding lesson that came through to me. Informed consent should not be viewed as a solitary event, but a conversation. This patient had expressed his desire to have surgery multiple times to my surgical resident and to his family. Even though we should never take the position that patients cannot change their minds, we should carefully question those choices that are inconsistent with the prior discussions that have been undertaken. Good communication skills – including listening to the patient, understanding the patient’s reasoning, and reflecting on the entire conversation – are essential in obtaining informed consent.
Dr. Angelos is the Linda Kohler Anderson Professor of Surgery and Surgical Ethics, chief of endocrine surgery, and associate director of the MacLean Center for Clinical Medical Ethics at the University of Chicago.
The Right Choice? Modifiable risk factors and surgical decision making
In the July 26, 2018, issue of the New England Journal of Medicine, Ira L. Leeds, MD, David T. Efron, MD, FACS, and Lisa S. Lehmann, MD, raise the important issue of how to proceed when a patient has an indication for surgery and wants the surgery, but the patient has modifiable risk factors that make the likelihood of surgical complications high.1 Specifically, the authors describe a 45-year-old woman with morbid obesity and chronic opioid dependency who presented with a large incisional hernia. The patient suffers from debilitating pain and nausea that has been attributed to her hernia. She is homebound and is seeking a third opinion on repair of the hernia. She has smoked for 30 years and continues to do so after prior unsuccessful attempts to quit. She has been turned down previously by two surgeons who reportedly felt she was too high risk. Application of an all-procedure risk calculator has shown a 38% higher than average risk of a complication with an expected length of stay 80% longer than average.
The authors appropriately place the decision making around this case in the context of a dilemma between allowing a patient to assume greater risks (and thereby respecting her autonomous choice) and giving the surgeon the opportunity to decline a riskier operation that will result in a greater expenditure of health care resources. The authors note that, by operating on such a high-risk patient, the surgeon and the hospital will likely receive lower scores on public ranking systems and even lower payments if reimbursement is related to performance-based outcomes. The potential improvement in the individual patient’s quality of life is thereby balanced against the risk of more complications and greater expenditure of health resources on this patient.
I commend the authors for raising this set of issues for consideration. As surgeons, we routinely make decisions about what operations we recommend to patients based on the risks of the operation. However, we also allow significant latitude for patients to make individual decisions about assuming greater or lesser risks. If the patient’s surgical risks could be reduced by her stopping smoking and losing weight, should the surgeon insist upon those things being done before being willing to operate on the patient? The answer to this question depends on the perspective that one takes in viewing this case. If the surgeon’s relationship with the patient is primary and the potential benefit of surgery is clearly present, then one could view the considerations of lower public ranking and added costs to society as irrelevant. However, if a surgeon views his or her role as not only advocating for their patient, but also being a steward of societal resources, then the added resources necessary to get this patient safely through the operation are critically important to consider.
In order to come to a decision for this individual patient, the authors argue in favor of greater patient education of the surgical risk so the patient can appreciate the importance of modifying the risky behaviors prior to surgery. This concept of shared decision making with patients is certainly important and should be encouraged in any surgeon-patient interaction around a possible surgical intervention. The authors also note the importance of ensuring an alignment of values between the patient and the surgeon in why the operation might be undertaken. These suggestions are excellent and undoubtedly would lead to better relationships between surgeons and patients and also likely better decisions about when to operate.
My primary concern with the authors’ suggestions occurs when the authors encourage surgical professional societies to “develop consistent practice guidelines without partiality to any particular patient.” The authors make the claim that, in a complex case in which it is difficult to decide what is best for the patient, we would benefit from having more guidelines about what modifiable risk factors should preclude surgery.
I worry that the appeal to guidelines is too often an appeal to ignore the individual aspects of a patient’s condition and the impact that the condition has on a patient’s life. Rather than saying, “What we need is more guidelines,” I would much prefer we emphasize the need for more communication between surgeons and patients about the risks of surgery and the implications of recovery on the patient’s quality of life. Although there is nothing detrimental to gathering data about the impact of modifiable risks on surgical outcomes, I am concerned that guidelines may become viewed as parameters of “good” patient care. We all know that no guideline can account for all the individual values and goals a patient may have and, thus, we ought not use guidelines to shield us from the complex individual decision making that as surgeons we should engage in with each of our patients.
Reference
1. Leeds IL et al. Surgical gatekeeping – modifiable risk factors and ethical decision making. N Engl J Med. 2018 Jul 26. doi:10.1056/NEJMms1802079.
Dr. Angelos is the Linda Kohler Anderson Professor of Surgery and Surgical Ethics, chief of endocrine surgery, and associate director of the MacLean Center for Clinical Medical Ethics at the University of Chicago.
In the July 26, 2018, issue of the New England Journal of Medicine, Ira L. Leeds, MD, David T. Efron, MD, FACS, and Lisa S. Lehmann, MD, raise the important issue of how to proceed when a patient has an indication for surgery and wants the surgery, but the patient has modifiable risk factors that make the likelihood of surgical complications high.1 Specifically, the authors describe a 45-year-old woman with morbid obesity and chronic opioid dependency who presented with a large incisional hernia. The patient suffers from debilitating pain and nausea that has been attributed to her hernia. She is homebound and is seeking a third opinion on repair of the hernia. She has smoked for 30 years and continues to do so after prior unsuccessful attempts to quit. She has been turned down previously by two surgeons who reportedly felt she was too high risk. Application of an all-procedure risk calculator has shown a 38% higher than average risk of a complication with an expected length of stay 80% longer than average.
The authors appropriately place the decision making around this case in the context of a dilemma between allowing a patient to assume greater risks (and thereby respecting her autonomous choice) and giving the surgeon the opportunity to decline a riskier operation that will result in a greater expenditure of health care resources. The authors note that, by operating on such a high-risk patient, the surgeon and the hospital will likely receive lower scores on public ranking systems and even lower payments if reimbursement is related to performance-based outcomes. The potential improvement in the individual patient’s quality of life is thereby balanced against the risk of more complications and greater expenditure of health resources on this patient.
I commend the authors for raising this set of issues for consideration. As surgeons, we routinely make decisions about what operations we recommend to patients based on the risks of the operation. However, we also allow significant latitude for patients to make individual decisions about assuming greater or lesser risks. If the patient’s surgical risks could be reduced by her stopping smoking and losing weight, should the surgeon insist upon those things being done before being willing to operate on the patient? The answer to this question depends on the perspective that one takes in viewing this case. If the surgeon’s relationship with the patient is primary and the potential benefit of surgery is clearly present, then one could view the considerations of lower public ranking and added costs to society as irrelevant. However, if a surgeon views his or her role as not only advocating for their patient, but also being a steward of societal resources, then the added resources necessary to get this patient safely through the operation are critically important to consider.
In order to come to a decision for this individual patient, the authors argue in favor of greater patient education of the surgical risk so the patient can appreciate the importance of modifying the risky behaviors prior to surgery. This concept of shared decision making with patients is certainly important and should be encouraged in any surgeon-patient interaction around a possible surgical intervention. The authors also note the importance of ensuring an alignment of values between the patient and the surgeon in why the operation might be undertaken. These suggestions are excellent and undoubtedly would lead to better relationships between surgeons and patients and also likely better decisions about when to operate.
My primary concern with the authors’ suggestions occurs when the authors encourage surgical professional societies to “develop consistent practice guidelines without partiality to any particular patient.” The authors make the claim that, in a complex case in which it is difficult to decide what is best for the patient, we would benefit from having more guidelines about what modifiable risk factors should preclude surgery.
I worry that the appeal to guidelines is too often an appeal to ignore the individual aspects of a patient’s condition and the impact that the condition has on a patient’s life. Rather than saying, “What we need is more guidelines,” I would much prefer we emphasize the need for more communication between surgeons and patients about the risks of surgery and the implications of recovery on the patient’s quality of life. Although there is nothing detrimental to gathering data about the impact of modifiable risks on surgical outcomes, I am concerned that guidelines may become viewed as parameters of “good” patient care. We all know that no guideline can account for all the individual values and goals a patient may have and, thus, we ought not use guidelines to shield us from the complex individual decision making that as surgeons we should engage in with each of our patients.
Reference
1. Leeds IL et al. Surgical gatekeeping – modifiable risk factors and ethical decision making. N Engl J Med. 2018 Jul 26. doi:10.1056/NEJMms1802079.
Dr. Angelos is the Linda Kohler Anderson Professor of Surgery and Surgical Ethics, chief of endocrine surgery, and associate director of the MacLean Center for Clinical Medical Ethics at the University of Chicago.
In the July 26, 2018, issue of the New England Journal of Medicine, Ira L. Leeds, MD, David T. Efron, MD, FACS, and Lisa S. Lehmann, MD, raise the important issue of how to proceed when a patient has an indication for surgery and wants the surgery, but the patient has modifiable risk factors that make the likelihood of surgical complications high.1 Specifically, the authors describe a 45-year-old woman with morbid obesity and chronic opioid dependency who presented with a large incisional hernia. The patient suffers from debilitating pain and nausea that has been attributed to her hernia. She is homebound and is seeking a third opinion on repair of the hernia. She has smoked for 30 years and continues to do so after prior unsuccessful attempts to quit. She has been turned down previously by two surgeons who reportedly felt she was too high risk. Application of an all-procedure risk calculator has shown a 38% higher than average risk of a complication with an expected length of stay 80% longer than average.
The authors appropriately place the decision making around this case in the context of a dilemma between allowing a patient to assume greater risks (and thereby respecting her autonomous choice) and giving the surgeon the opportunity to decline a riskier operation that will result in a greater expenditure of health care resources. The authors note that, by operating on such a high-risk patient, the surgeon and the hospital will likely receive lower scores on public ranking systems and even lower payments if reimbursement is related to performance-based outcomes. The potential improvement in the individual patient’s quality of life is thereby balanced against the risk of more complications and greater expenditure of health resources on this patient.
I commend the authors for raising this set of issues for consideration. As surgeons, we routinely make decisions about what operations we recommend to patients based on the risks of the operation. However, we also allow significant latitude for patients to make individual decisions about assuming greater or lesser risks. If the patient’s surgical risks could be reduced by her stopping smoking and losing weight, should the surgeon insist upon those things being done before being willing to operate on the patient? The answer to this question depends on the perspective that one takes in viewing this case. If the surgeon’s relationship with the patient is primary and the potential benefit of surgery is clearly present, then one could view the considerations of lower public ranking and added costs to society as irrelevant. However, if a surgeon views his or her role as not only advocating for their patient, but also being a steward of societal resources, then the added resources necessary to get this patient safely through the operation are critically important to consider.
In order to come to a decision for this individual patient, the authors argue in favor of greater patient education of the surgical risk so the patient can appreciate the importance of modifying the risky behaviors prior to surgery. This concept of shared decision making with patients is certainly important and should be encouraged in any surgeon-patient interaction around a possible surgical intervention. The authors also note the importance of ensuring an alignment of values between the patient and the surgeon in why the operation might be undertaken. These suggestions are excellent and undoubtedly would lead to better relationships between surgeons and patients and also likely better decisions about when to operate.
My primary concern with the authors’ suggestions occurs when the authors encourage surgical professional societies to “develop consistent practice guidelines without partiality to any particular patient.” The authors make the claim that, in a complex case in which it is difficult to decide what is best for the patient, we would benefit from having more guidelines about what modifiable risk factors should preclude surgery.
I worry that the appeal to guidelines is too often an appeal to ignore the individual aspects of a patient’s condition and the impact that the condition has on a patient’s life. Rather than saying, “What we need is more guidelines,” I would much prefer we emphasize the need for more communication between surgeons and patients about the risks of surgery and the implications of recovery on the patient’s quality of life. Although there is nothing detrimental to gathering data about the impact of modifiable risks on surgical outcomes, I am concerned that guidelines may become viewed as parameters of “good” patient care. We all know that no guideline can account for all the individual values and goals a patient may have and, thus, we ought not use guidelines to shield us from the complex individual decision making that as surgeons we should engage in with each of our patients.
Reference
1. Leeds IL et al. Surgical gatekeeping – modifiable risk factors and ethical decision making. N Engl J Med. 2018 Jul 26. doi:10.1056/NEJMms1802079.
Dr. Angelos is the Linda Kohler Anderson Professor of Surgery and Surgical Ethics, chief of endocrine surgery, and associate director of the MacLean Center for Clinical Medical Ethics at the University of Chicago.
The right choice? Surgery “offered” or “recommended”?
The story was not unusual for a late-night surgical consultation request by the emergency department. The patient was a 32-year-old man who had presented to the emergency room with crampy abdominal pain. He initially had felt distended, but – during the 3 hours since his presentation to the hospital – the pain and distention had resolved. A CT of the abdomen and pelvis was obtained shortly after the patient arrived in the emergency department. The study showed some dilated small bowel along with a worrisome spiral pattern of the mesentery that suggested a midgut volvulus. The finding was surprising to the surgical resident examining the patient given that the patient now had a soft and nontender abdomen on exam. The white blood cell count was not elevated, and the electrolyte levels were all normal.
The surgical resident’s assessment was that, despite the unremarkable abdominal exam and the resolution of the patient’s pain, surgery was indicated. The resident discussed the patient’s case with the attending surgeon on call that night, and the attending agreed: The patient should have an abdominal exploration to rule out a midgut volvulus and the potential for an abdominal catastrophe.
When presented with this recommendation, the patient declined the recommended surgery. He stated that he felt fine and that this would be a bad time to have an operation and miss work. The patient ultimately left the hospital only to present 5 days later with peritonitis. When he was emergently explored on the second admission, he was found to have a significant amount of gangrenous small bowel that required resection.
The case was presented at the M and M (morbidity and mortality) conference the following week. When asked about the prior hospital admission, the resident reported that the patient had been “offered surgery,” and in the context of “shared decision making,” the patient had chosen to go home. This characterization of the interactions with the patient raised concern among several of the attending surgeons present. Was the patient only “offered” surgery, or was he strongly recommended to have surgery to avoid potentially risking his life? Was the patient’s refusal to have surgery despite the risks actually a case of “shared decision making”?
These questions are but a few of the many that can arise when language is used indiscriminately. Although, in the contemporary era of “patient-centered decision making,” it is common to think about every recommendation as an offer of alternative therapies, I worry that describing the interaction in this fashion is potentially misleading. Patients should not be offered potentially life-saving treatments – those treatments should be strongly recommended. Certainly, we must accept that patients can refuse even the most strongly recommended treatments, but a patient’s refusal to follow a strong recommendation for surgery should not be characterized as shared decision making. “Shared decision making” suggests that there are medically acceptable choices that the physician has offered the patient, from which the patient can make a choice based on his or her preferences and values. The case above is not shared decision making but one of respecting the patient’s autonomous choices even if we do not agree with the choices made.
There are undoubtedly situations in which there is a choice among reasonable medical options. When there is a such a choice to be made, as surgeons, we should help our patients understand the options so that they can make a decision that best fits with their values and goals. However, when the only choice is whether to have the recommended surgery or decline it, we have now moved beyond shared decision making. In that circumstance, we should strongly recommend what we believe is the better option while still respecting the autonomy of patients to decline our recommendation.
Shared decision making often is viewed as the pinnacle of ethical practice – that is, involving patients in the decisions to be made about their own health. Although I agree that we do want to educate our patients and encourage them to make what we consider safe medical decisions, when we recommend a safe choice and the patient declines it, we are no longer talking about shared decision making. In such circumstances, we are in the realm of respecting patients’ choices even when we disagree with those choices. Our responsibility as surgeons is to recommend what we think is safe but respect their choices whether we agree or not. We should do more than simply offer surgery when it is potentially life threatening not to have it.
Dr. Angelos is the Linda Kohler Anderson Professor of Surgery and Surgical Ethics, chief of endocrine surgery, and associate director of the MacLean Center for Clinical Medical Ethics at the University of Chicago.
The story was not unusual for a late-night surgical consultation request by the emergency department. The patient was a 32-year-old man who had presented to the emergency room with crampy abdominal pain. He initially had felt distended, but – during the 3 hours since his presentation to the hospital – the pain and distention had resolved. A CT of the abdomen and pelvis was obtained shortly after the patient arrived in the emergency department. The study showed some dilated small bowel along with a worrisome spiral pattern of the mesentery that suggested a midgut volvulus. The finding was surprising to the surgical resident examining the patient given that the patient now had a soft and nontender abdomen on exam. The white blood cell count was not elevated, and the electrolyte levels were all normal.
The surgical resident’s assessment was that, despite the unremarkable abdominal exam and the resolution of the patient’s pain, surgery was indicated. The resident discussed the patient’s case with the attending surgeon on call that night, and the attending agreed: The patient should have an abdominal exploration to rule out a midgut volvulus and the potential for an abdominal catastrophe.
When presented with this recommendation, the patient declined the recommended surgery. He stated that he felt fine and that this would be a bad time to have an operation and miss work. The patient ultimately left the hospital only to present 5 days later with peritonitis. When he was emergently explored on the second admission, he was found to have a significant amount of gangrenous small bowel that required resection.
The case was presented at the M and M (morbidity and mortality) conference the following week. When asked about the prior hospital admission, the resident reported that the patient had been “offered surgery,” and in the context of “shared decision making,” the patient had chosen to go home. This characterization of the interactions with the patient raised concern among several of the attending surgeons present. Was the patient only “offered” surgery, or was he strongly recommended to have surgery to avoid potentially risking his life? Was the patient’s refusal to have surgery despite the risks actually a case of “shared decision making”?
These questions are but a few of the many that can arise when language is used indiscriminately. Although, in the contemporary era of “patient-centered decision making,” it is common to think about every recommendation as an offer of alternative therapies, I worry that describing the interaction in this fashion is potentially misleading. Patients should not be offered potentially life-saving treatments – those treatments should be strongly recommended. Certainly, we must accept that patients can refuse even the most strongly recommended treatments, but a patient’s refusal to follow a strong recommendation for surgery should not be characterized as shared decision making. “Shared decision making” suggests that there are medically acceptable choices that the physician has offered the patient, from which the patient can make a choice based on his or her preferences and values. The case above is not shared decision making but one of respecting the patient’s autonomous choices even if we do not agree with the choices made.
There are undoubtedly situations in which there is a choice among reasonable medical options. When there is a such a choice to be made, as surgeons, we should help our patients understand the options so that they can make a decision that best fits with their values and goals. However, when the only choice is whether to have the recommended surgery or decline it, we have now moved beyond shared decision making. In that circumstance, we should strongly recommend what we believe is the better option while still respecting the autonomy of patients to decline our recommendation.
Shared decision making often is viewed as the pinnacle of ethical practice – that is, involving patients in the decisions to be made about their own health. Although I agree that we do want to educate our patients and encourage them to make what we consider safe medical decisions, when we recommend a safe choice and the patient declines it, we are no longer talking about shared decision making. In such circumstances, we are in the realm of respecting patients’ choices even when we disagree with those choices. Our responsibility as surgeons is to recommend what we think is safe but respect their choices whether we agree or not. We should do more than simply offer surgery when it is potentially life threatening not to have it.
Dr. Angelos is the Linda Kohler Anderson Professor of Surgery and Surgical Ethics, chief of endocrine surgery, and associate director of the MacLean Center for Clinical Medical Ethics at the University of Chicago.
The story was not unusual for a late-night surgical consultation request by the emergency department. The patient was a 32-year-old man who had presented to the emergency room with crampy abdominal pain. He initially had felt distended, but – during the 3 hours since his presentation to the hospital – the pain and distention had resolved. A CT of the abdomen and pelvis was obtained shortly after the patient arrived in the emergency department. The study showed some dilated small bowel along with a worrisome spiral pattern of the mesentery that suggested a midgut volvulus. The finding was surprising to the surgical resident examining the patient given that the patient now had a soft and nontender abdomen on exam. The white blood cell count was not elevated, and the electrolyte levels were all normal.
The surgical resident’s assessment was that, despite the unremarkable abdominal exam and the resolution of the patient’s pain, surgery was indicated. The resident discussed the patient’s case with the attending surgeon on call that night, and the attending agreed: The patient should have an abdominal exploration to rule out a midgut volvulus and the potential for an abdominal catastrophe.
When presented with this recommendation, the patient declined the recommended surgery. He stated that he felt fine and that this would be a bad time to have an operation and miss work. The patient ultimately left the hospital only to present 5 days later with peritonitis. When he was emergently explored on the second admission, he was found to have a significant amount of gangrenous small bowel that required resection.
The case was presented at the M and M (morbidity and mortality) conference the following week. When asked about the prior hospital admission, the resident reported that the patient had been “offered surgery,” and in the context of “shared decision making,” the patient had chosen to go home. This characterization of the interactions with the patient raised concern among several of the attending surgeons present. Was the patient only “offered” surgery, or was he strongly recommended to have surgery to avoid potentially risking his life? Was the patient’s refusal to have surgery despite the risks actually a case of “shared decision making”?
These questions are but a few of the many that can arise when language is used indiscriminately. Although, in the contemporary era of “patient-centered decision making,” it is common to think about every recommendation as an offer of alternative therapies, I worry that describing the interaction in this fashion is potentially misleading. Patients should not be offered potentially life-saving treatments – those treatments should be strongly recommended. Certainly, we must accept that patients can refuse even the most strongly recommended treatments, but a patient’s refusal to follow a strong recommendation for surgery should not be characterized as shared decision making. “Shared decision making” suggests that there are medically acceptable choices that the physician has offered the patient, from which the patient can make a choice based on his or her preferences and values. The case above is not shared decision making but one of respecting the patient’s autonomous choices even if we do not agree with the choices made.
There are undoubtedly situations in which there is a choice among reasonable medical options. When there is a such a choice to be made, as surgeons, we should help our patients understand the options so that they can make a decision that best fits with their values and goals. However, when the only choice is whether to have the recommended surgery or decline it, we have now moved beyond shared decision making. In that circumstance, we should strongly recommend what we believe is the better option while still respecting the autonomy of patients to decline our recommendation.
Shared decision making often is viewed as the pinnacle of ethical practice – that is, involving patients in the decisions to be made about their own health. Although I agree that we do want to educate our patients and encourage them to make what we consider safe medical decisions, when we recommend a safe choice and the patient declines it, we are no longer talking about shared decision making. In such circumstances, we are in the realm of respecting patients’ choices even when we disagree with those choices. Our responsibility as surgeons is to recommend what we think is safe but respect their choices whether we agree or not. We should do more than simply offer surgery when it is potentially life threatening not to have it.
Dr. Angelos is the Linda Kohler Anderson Professor of Surgery and Surgical Ethics, chief of endocrine surgery, and associate director of the MacLean Center for Clinical Medical Ethics at the University of Chicago.
The right choice? Surgeons, confidence, and humility
It started as an offhand comment. The patient had been on the medicine service for over a week before developing acute appendicitis with an abscess and requiring an emergency open appendectomy. He was a 68-year-old man who had longstanding medical issues that had given him many opportunities to interact with physicians in the prior few years.
On the second morning after surgery, a new team of surgical residents was rounding on him. The chief resident led the group of residents and students into the patient’s room and introduced himself as being part of the surgical team. The patient smiled and stated that he knew this was a group of surgeons. When asked why, the patient reported that he could always tell when surgeons enter the room. “You enter with an air of bravado and arrogance that the medical doctors do not exude.” The surgical residents commented on this fact to me later when I rounded on the patient, and it prompted discussion of the potential positives and negatives of confidence in surgical practice.
Most successful surgeons express a level of confidence in their abilities that often exceeds that of many other physicians. Such observations have led to the joke that “surgeons are often wrong, but never in doubt.” The question is whether the expression of confidence in one’s abilities as a surgeon is a requirement of a surgeon or simply a common characteristic for many people who choose to go into the field of surgery.
There is no doubt in my mind that in order to be willing to put a patient through an operation, surgeons must be confident in their skills. Surgery never achieves its benefit for patients without first causing the patient some harm. Any operation requires that the surgeon impose a violent act on the patient that, in any other context, would be illegal. In order to do such things to patients, surgeons must have a high degree of confidence.
Patients also appreciate a confident surgeon. Over the years, I have known many technically excellent surgeons who have never been as busy as they might have been because they were unable to express confidence to their patients. The opposite, however, is also true. There are surgeons who become so overconfident in their abilities that they become reckless in recommending high-risk operations to patients.
Given that patients expect their surgeons to have confidence and surgeons actually need to be confident in order to be successful, it might be surprising that the important attribute of self-confidence does not more frequently spill over into overbearing arrogance. Perhaps the most important temporizing of surgeon overconfidence is the unfortunate inevitable consequence of surgery that complications happen to even the best surgeons. We all know that the central question of the M & M conference is, “What could you have done differently?” Whether this question is answered publicly or only in the mind of the surgeon, the contemplation of the decisions made, and their consequences, is essential for each surgeon to consider in the face of every complication.
Much as the public should want surgeons to be confident, but not too confident, they should also want their surgeons to take complications seriously, but not too seriously. It is helpful for a surgeon to think about making a different choice in the future. But it would not be helpful if, in the face of a bad outcome, a surgeon decides that he or she can no longer perform surgery.
This balance between lack of confidence and overconfidence, and between thoughtful introspection and paralyzing fear of future complications, is challenging to teach to surgical residents and fellows. Part of the challenge is that often surgical faculty do not verbalize the challenges that we face in this realm. The perfect combination of confidence and humility is something that few of us have identified in our own lives, let alone are prepared to teach it authoritatively to others. Nevertheless, teaching the next generation of surgeons to recognize the tension between confidence and humility is worthwhile. And like their elders, they may well discover that achieving the right balance is a lifelong pursuit.
Dr. Angelos is the Linda Kohler Anderson Professor of Surgery and Surgical Ethics; chief, endocrine surgery; and associate director of the MacLean Center for Clinical Medical Ethics at the University of Chicago.
It started as an offhand comment. The patient had been on the medicine service for over a week before developing acute appendicitis with an abscess and requiring an emergency open appendectomy. He was a 68-year-old man who had longstanding medical issues that had given him many opportunities to interact with physicians in the prior few years.
On the second morning after surgery, a new team of surgical residents was rounding on him. The chief resident led the group of residents and students into the patient’s room and introduced himself as being part of the surgical team. The patient smiled and stated that he knew this was a group of surgeons. When asked why, the patient reported that he could always tell when surgeons enter the room. “You enter with an air of bravado and arrogance that the medical doctors do not exude.” The surgical residents commented on this fact to me later when I rounded on the patient, and it prompted discussion of the potential positives and negatives of confidence in surgical practice.
Most successful surgeons express a level of confidence in their abilities that often exceeds that of many other physicians. Such observations have led to the joke that “surgeons are often wrong, but never in doubt.” The question is whether the expression of confidence in one’s abilities as a surgeon is a requirement of a surgeon or simply a common characteristic for many people who choose to go into the field of surgery.
There is no doubt in my mind that in order to be willing to put a patient through an operation, surgeons must be confident in their skills. Surgery never achieves its benefit for patients without first causing the patient some harm. Any operation requires that the surgeon impose a violent act on the patient that, in any other context, would be illegal. In order to do such things to patients, surgeons must have a high degree of confidence.
Patients also appreciate a confident surgeon. Over the years, I have known many technically excellent surgeons who have never been as busy as they might have been because they were unable to express confidence to their patients. The opposite, however, is also true. There are surgeons who become so overconfident in their abilities that they become reckless in recommending high-risk operations to patients.
Given that patients expect their surgeons to have confidence and surgeons actually need to be confident in order to be successful, it might be surprising that the important attribute of self-confidence does not more frequently spill over into overbearing arrogance. Perhaps the most important temporizing of surgeon overconfidence is the unfortunate inevitable consequence of surgery that complications happen to even the best surgeons. We all know that the central question of the M & M conference is, “What could you have done differently?” Whether this question is answered publicly or only in the mind of the surgeon, the contemplation of the decisions made, and their consequences, is essential for each surgeon to consider in the face of every complication.
Much as the public should want surgeons to be confident, but not too confident, they should also want their surgeons to take complications seriously, but not too seriously. It is helpful for a surgeon to think about making a different choice in the future. But it would not be helpful if, in the face of a bad outcome, a surgeon decides that he or she can no longer perform surgery.
This balance between lack of confidence and overconfidence, and between thoughtful introspection and paralyzing fear of future complications, is challenging to teach to surgical residents and fellows. Part of the challenge is that often surgical faculty do not verbalize the challenges that we face in this realm. The perfect combination of confidence and humility is something that few of us have identified in our own lives, let alone are prepared to teach it authoritatively to others. Nevertheless, teaching the next generation of surgeons to recognize the tension between confidence and humility is worthwhile. And like their elders, they may well discover that achieving the right balance is a lifelong pursuit.
Dr. Angelos is the Linda Kohler Anderson Professor of Surgery and Surgical Ethics; chief, endocrine surgery; and associate director of the MacLean Center for Clinical Medical Ethics at the University of Chicago.
It started as an offhand comment. The patient had been on the medicine service for over a week before developing acute appendicitis with an abscess and requiring an emergency open appendectomy. He was a 68-year-old man who had longstanding medical issues that had given him many opportunities to interact with physicians in the prior few years.
On the second morning after surgery, a new team of surgical residents was rounding on him. The chief resident led the group of residents and students into the patient’s room and introduced himself as being part of the surgical team. The patient smiled and stated that he knew this was a group of surgeons. When asked why, the patient reported that he could always tell when surgeons enter the room. “You enter with an air of bravado and arrogance that the medical doctors do not exude.” The surgical residents commented on this fact to me later when I rounded on the patient, and it prompted discussion of the potential positives and negatives of confidence in surgical practice.
Most successful surgeons express a level of confidence in their abilities that often exceeds that of many other physicians. Such observations have led to the joke that “surgeons are often wrong, but never in doubt.” The question is whether the expression of confidence in one’s abilities as a surgeon is a requirement of a surgeon or simply a common characteristic for many people who choose to go into the field of surgery.
There is no doubt in my mind that in order to be willing to put a patient through an operation, surgeons must be confident in their skills. Surgery never achieves its benefit for patients without first causing the patient some harm. Any operation requires that the surgeon impose a violent act on the patient that, in any other context, would be illegal. In order to do such things to patients, surgeons must have a high degree of confidence.
Patients also appreciate a confident surgeon. Over the years, I have known many technically excellent surgeons who have never been as busy as they might have been because they were unable to express confidence to their patients. The opposite, however, is also true. There are surgeons who become so overconfident in their abilities that they become reckless in recommending high-risk operations to patients.
Given that patients expect their surgeons to have confidence and surgeons actually need to be confident in order to be successful, it might be surprising that the important attribute of self-confidence does not more frequently spill over into overbearing arrogance. Perhaps the most important temporizing of surgeon overconfidence is the unfortunate inevitable consequence of surgery that complications happen to even the best surgeons. We all know that the central question of the M & M conference is, “What could you have done differently?” Whether this question is answered publicly or only in the mind of the surgeon, the contemplation of the decisions made, and their consequences, is essential for each surgeon to consider in the face of every complication.
Much as the public should want surgeons to be confident, but not too confident, they should also want their surgeons to take complications seriously, but not too seriously. It is helpful for a surgeon to think about making a different choice in the future. But it would not be helpful if, in the face of a bad outcome, a surgeon decides that he or she can no longer perform surgery.
This balance between lack of confidence and overconfidence, and between thoughtful introspection and paralyzing fear of future complications, is challenging to teach to surgical residents and fellows. Part of the challenge is that often surgical faculty do not verbalize the challenges that we face in this realm. The perfect combination of confidence and humility is something that few of us have identified in our own lives, let alone are prepared to teach it authoritatively to others. Nevertheless, teaching the next generation of surgeons to recognize the tension between confidence and humility is worthwhile. And like their elders, they may well discover that achieving the right balance is a lifelong pursuit.
Dr. Angelos is the Linda Kohler Anderson Professor of Surgery and Surgical Ethics; chief, endocrine surgery; and associate director of the MacLean Center for Clinical Medical Ethics at the University of Chicago.
The Right Choice? Surgeons, confidence, and humility
It started as an offhand comment. The patient had been on the medicine service for over a week before developing acute appendicitis with an abscess requiring an emergency open appendectomy. He was a 68-year-old man who had longstanding medical issues that had given him many opportunities to interact with physicians in the prior few years.
On the second morning after surgery, a new team of surgical residents was rounding on him. The chief resident led the group of residents and students into the patient’s room and introduced himself as being part of the surgical team. The patient smiled and stated that he knew this was a group of surgeons. When asked why, the patient reported that he could always tell when surgeons enter the room. “You enter with an air of bravado and arrogance that the medical doctors do not exude.” The surgical residents commented on this fact to me later when I rounded on the patient, and it prompted discussion of the potential positives and negatives of confidence in surgical practice.
Most successful surgeons express a level of confidence in their abilities which often exceeds that of many other physicians. Such observations have led to the joke that “surgeons are often wrong, but never in doubt.” The question is whether the expression of confidence in one’s abilities as a surgeon is a requirement of a surgeon or simply a common characteristic for many people who choose to go into the field of surgery.
There is no doubt in my mind that in order to be willing to put a patient through an operation, surgeons must be confident in their skills. Surgery never achieves its benefit for patients without first causing the patient some harm. Any operation requires that the surgeon impose a violent act on the patient that, in any other context, would be illegal. To do such things to patients, surgeons must have a high degree of confidence.
Patients also appreciate a confident surgeon. Over the years, I have known many technically excellent surgeons who have never been as busy as they might have because of their inability to express confidence to their patients. The opposite, however, is also true. There are surgeons who become so overconfident in their abilities that they become reckless in recommending high-risk operations to patients.
Given that patients expect their surgeons to be confident and surgeons actually need to be confident to be successful, it might be surprising that the important attribute of self-confidence does not more frequently spill over into overbearing arrogance. Perhaps the most important temporizing of surgeon overconfidence is the unfortunate inevitable consequence of surgery that complications happen to even the best surgeons. We all know that the central question of the M & M conference is, “What could you have done differently?” Whether this question is answered publicly or only in the mind of the surgeon, the contemplation of the decisions made, and their consequences, is essential for each surgeon to consider in the face of every complication.
Much as the public should want surgeons to be confident, but not too confident, they should also want their surgeons to take complications seriously, but not too seriously. It is helpful for a surgeon to think about making a different choice in the future. But it would not be helpful if, in the face of a bad outcome, a surgeon decides that he or she can no longer perform surgery.
This balance between lack of confidence and overconfidence, and between thoughtful introspection and paralyzing fear of future complications, is challenging to teach to surgical residents and fellows. Part of the challenge is that often surgical faculty do not verbalize the challenges that we face in this realm. The perfect combination of confidence and humility is something that few of us have identified in our own lives, let alone are prepared to teach authoritatively to others. Nevertheless, teaching the next generation of surgeons to recognize the tension between confidence and humility is worthwhile. And like their elders, they may well discover that achieving the right balance is a lifelong pursuit.
Dr. Angelos is the Linda Kohler Anderson Professor of Surgery and Surgical Ethics; chief, endocrine surgery; and associate director of the MacLean Center for Clinical Medical Ethics at the University of Chicago.
It started as an offhand comment. The patient had been on the medicine service for over a week before developing acute appendicitis with an abscess requiring an emergency open appendectomy. He was a 68-year-old man who had longstanding medical issues that had given him many opportunities to interact with physicians in the prior few years.
On the second morning after surgery, a new team of surgical residents was rounding on him. The chief resident led the group of residents and students into the patient’s room and introduced himself as being part of the surgical team. The patient smiled and stated that he knew this was a group of surgeons. When asked why, the patient reported that he could always tell when surgeons enter the room. “You enter with an air of bravado and arrogance that the medical doctors do not exude.” The surgical residents commented on this fact to me later when I rounded on the patient, and it prompted discussion of the potential positives and negatives of confidence in surgical practice.
Most successful surgeons express a level of confidence in their abilities which often exceeds that of many other physicians. Such observations have led to the joke that “surgeons are often wrong, but never in doubt.” The question is whether the expression of confidence in one’s abilities as a surgeon is a requirement of a surgeon or simply a common characteristic for many people who choose to go into the field of surgery.
There is no doubt in my mind that in order to be willing to put a patient through an operation, surgeons must be confident in their skills. Surgery never achieves its benefit for patients without first causing the patient some harm. Any operation requires that the surgeon impose a violent act on the patient that, in any other context, would be illegal. To do such things to patients, surgeons must have a high degree of confidence.
Patients also appreciate a confident surgeon. Over the years, I have known many technically excellent surgeons who have never been as busy as they might have because of their inability to express confidence to their patients. The opposite, however, is also true. There are surgeons who become so overconfident in their abilities that they become reckless in recommending high-risk operations to patients.
Given that patients expect their surgeons to be confident and surgeons actually need to be confident to be successful, it might be surprising that the important attribute of self-confidence does not more frequently spill over into overbearing arrogance. Perhaps the most important temporizing of surgeon overconfidence is the unfortunate inevitable consequence of surgery that complications happen to even the best surgeons. We all know that the central question of the M & M conference is, “What could you have done differently?” Whether this question is answered publicly or only in the mind of the surgeon, the contemplation of the decisions made, and their consequences, is essential for each surgeon to consider in the face of every complication.
Much as the public should want surgeons to be confident, but not too confident, they should also want their surgeons to take complications seriously, but not too seriously. It is helpful for a surgeon to think about making a different choice in the future. But it would not be helpful if, in the face of a bad outcome, a surgeon decides that he or she can no longer perform surgery.
This balance between lack of confidence and overconfidence, and between thoughtful introspection and paralyzing fear of future complications, is challenging to teach to surgical residents and fellows. Part of the challenge is that often surgical faculty do not verbalize the challenges that we face in this realm. The perfect combination of confidence and humility is something that few of us have identified in our own lives, let alone are prepared to teach authoritatively to others. Nevertheless, teaching the next generation of surgeons to recognize the tension between confidence and humility is worthwhile. And like their elders, they may well discover that achieving the right balance is a lifelong pursuit.
Dr. Angelos is the Linda Kohler Anderson Professor of Surgery and Surgical Ethics; chief, endocrine surgery; and associate director of the MacLean Center for Clinical Medical Ethics at the University of Chicago.
It started as an offhand comment. The patient had been on the medicine service for over a week before developing acute appendicitis with an abscess requiring an emergency open appendectomy. He was a 68-year-old man who had longstanding medical issues that had given him many opportunities to interact with physicians in the prior few years.
On the second morning after surgery, a new team of surgical residents was rounding on him. The chief resident led the group of residents and students into the patient’s room and introduced himself as being part of the surgical team. The patient smiled and stated that he knew this was a group of surgeons. When asked why, the patient reported that he could always tell when surgeons enter the room. “You enter with an air of bravado and arrogance that the medical doctors do not exude.” The surgical residents commented on this fact to me later when I rounded on the patient, and it prompted discussion of the potential positives and negatives of confidence in surgical practice.
Most successful surgeons express a level of confidence in their abilities which often exceeds that of many other physicians. Such observations have led to the joke that “surgeons are often wrong, but never in doubt.” The question is whether the expression of confidence in one’s abilities as a surgeon is a requirement of a surgeon or simply a common characteristic for many people who choose to go into the field of surgery.
There is no doubt in my mind that in order to be willing to put a patient through an operation, surgeons must be confident in their skills. Surgery never achieves its benefit for patients without first causing the patient some harm. Any operation requires that the surgeon impose a violent act on the patient that, in any other context, would be illegal. To do such things to patients, surgeons must have a high degree of confidence.
Patients also appreciate a confident surgeon. Over the years, I have known many technically excellent surgeons who have never been as busy as they might have because of their inability to express confidence to their patients. The opposite, however, is also true. There are surgeons who become so overconfident in their abilities that they become reckless in recommending high-risk operations to patients.
Given that patients expect their surgeons to be confident and surgeons actually need to be confident to be successful, it might be surprising that the important attribute of self-confidence does not more frequently spill over into overbearing arrogance. Perhaps the most important temporizing of surgeon overconfidence is the unfortunate inevitable consequence of surgery that complications happen to even the best surgeons. We all know that the central question of the M & M conference is, “What could you have done differently?” Whether this question is answered publicly or only in the mind of the surgeon, the contemplation of the decisions made, and their consequences, is essential for each surgeon to consider in the face of every complication.
Much as the public should want surgeons to be confident, but not too confident, they should also want their surgeons to take complications seriously, but not too seriously. It is helpful for a surgeon to think about making a different choice in the future. But it would not be helpful if, in the face of a bad outcome, a surgeon decides that he or she can no longer perform surgery.
This balance between lack of confidence and overconfidence, and between thoughtful introspection and paralyzing fear of future complications, is challenging to teach to surgical residents and fellows. Part of the challenge is that often surgical faculty do not verbalize the challenges that we face in this realm. The perfect combination of confidence and humility is something that few of us have identified in our own lives, let alone are prepared to teach authoritatively to others. Nevertheless, teaching the next generation of surgeons to recognize the tension between confidence and humility is worthwhile. And like their elders, they may well discover that achieving the right balance is a lifelong pursuit.
Dr. Angelos is the Linda Kohler Anderson Professor of Surgery and Surgical Ethics; chief, endocrine surgery; and associate director of the MacLean Center for Clinical Medical Ethics at the University of Chicago.
The Problem of ‘Is’ and ‘Ought’ for Surgeons
Many years ago during medical school, I took time out to pursue graduate studies in philosophy. At that time, I took a number of courses that explored various approaches to the philosophical questions of morality and ethics. My ultimate goal, even back then, was to focus on ethical issues in the practice of medicine.
I often found the philosophical discussions from the “giants” in philosophy were not always easy to apply to everyday problems. After completing my graduate studies in philosophy and nearing the end of medical school, I found that I was drawn to surgery. Not surprisingly, many surgical faculty that I interviewed with for my residency saw little application of my philosophy studies to the practice of surgery. Although I felt confident that ethics was central to the practice of surgery, I let pass the general suggestions from many senior surgeons that surgery and philosophical analysis have little in common.
In recent years, however, I have increasingly seen an area of overlap that I believe will be central to the future of surgery. The options for the treatment of critically ill surgical patients across all areas of surgery have increased dramatically. Just in the area of cardiovascular disease, patients with failing hearts have the option of mechanical assist devices. Patients with multiple comorbidities and vascular problems can have numerous endovascular procedures done that years ago would have been unthinkable. Consider a patient with a ventricular assist device on a ventilator who is being dialyzed. Such a patient may be supported for weeks or months beyond what was possible just a few decades ago.
Whereas our surgical forefathers were constantly asking the question, “What can be done for this patient?” those caring for critically ill patients today must repeatedly ask, “What should we do for this patient?” Years ago, the statement, “there is nothing more that we can offer” was much more commonly heard than it is today. The critical question for today – “What should be done?” – is often more challenging and nuanced than “what can be done?” Whenever we ask “what should be done?” we must take into account the values of the patient and weigh the possible outcomes and the inherent risks of the possible interventions with the patient’s goals.
The current necessity to answer “what should be done?” has several striking parallels with the classical philosophical problem of “is” and “ought.” Over the centuries, many philosophers have considered whether we can derive an “ought” from an “is.” In other words, just because one can show that something is the case in the world, it does not automatically follow that it ought to be that way. David Hume, the Scottish philosopher (1711-1776), famously argued that there is a tremendous difference between statements about what is and statements about what ought to be. In particular, Hume argued that we cannot logically derive an “ought” from an “is.”
Despite the centuries that have passed since Hume’s days, I believe that his analysis has much to teach modern surgery. Just because we can undertake many interventions for our patients, it does not follow that we should undertake all of those interventions. A central aspect of what many of us refer to commonly as “surgical judgment” is deciding among the many possible interventions for a patient, what specific ones ought we offer. Although this entire discussion may seem theoretical (and possibly even arcane) to some surgeons, I firmly believe that one of the greatest challenges to the future of surgery is whether surgeons are willing to address the question of what should be done for every patient.
Excellent surgeons have traditionally been seen as having both technical mastery and sound judgment. In the current era in which surgeons are increasingly pushed to do more cases and maximize RVUs, multiple forces are encouraging surgeons to increasingly become pure technicians. Technicians can answer the question “what can be done?” However, “what should be done for this specific patient?” is a question that only a physician can answer. In the decades to come, we must ensure that surgeons continue to engage in the harder questions of “what should be done?” so that we do not forget that “is” and “ought” are different. The mastery of surgery involves not only the technical expertise that can be applied on behalf of a patient, but also the appreciation and understanding of the patient’s values so that surgeons can make recommendations about what should be done for their patients.
Dr. Angelos is the Linda Kohler Anderson Professor of Surgery and Surgical Ethics; chief, endocrine surgery; and associate director of the MacLean Center for Clinical Medical Ethics at the University of Chicago.
Many years ago during medical school, I took time out to pursue graduate studies in philosophy. At that time, I took a number of courses that explored various approaches to the philosophical questions of morality and ethics. My ultimate goal, even back then, was to focus on ethical issues in the practice of medicine.
I often found the philosophical discussions from the “giants” in philosophy were not always easy to apply to everyday problems. After completing my graduate studies in philosophy and nearing the end of medical school, I found that I was drawn to surgery. Not surprisingly, many surgical faculty that I interviewed with for my residency saw little application of my philosophy studies to the practice of surgery. Although I felt confident that ethics was central to the practice of surgery, I let pass the general suggestions from many senior surgeons that surgery and philosophical analysis have little in common.
In recent years, however, I have increasingly seen an area of overlap that I believe will be central to the future of surgery. The options for the treatment of critically ill surgical patients across all areas of surgery have increased dramatically. Just in the area of cardiovascular disease, patients with failing hearts have the option of mechanical assist devices. Patients with multiple comorbidities and vascular problems can have numerous endovascular procedures done that years ago would have been unthinkable. Consider a patient with a ventricular assist device on a ventilator who is being dialyzed. Such a patient may be supported for weeks or months beyond what was possible just a few decades ago.
Whereas our surgical forefathers were constantly asking the question, “What can be done for this patient?” those caring for critically ill patients today must repeatedly ask, “What should we do for this patient?” Years ago, the statement, “there is nothing more that we can offer” was much more commonly heard than it is today. The critical question for today – “What should be done?” – is often more challenging and nuanced than “what can be done?” Whenever we ask “what should be done?” we must take into account the values of the patient and weigh the possible outcomes and the inherent risks of the possible interventions with the patient’s goals.
The current necessity to answer “what should be done?” has several striking parallels with the classical philosophical problem of “is” and “ought.” Over the centuries, many philosophers have considered whether we can derive an “ought” from an “is.” In other words, just because one can show that something is the case in the world, it does not automatically follow that it ought to be that way. David Hume, the Scottish philosopher (1711-1776), famously argued that there is a tremendous difference between statements about what is and statements about what ought to be. In particular, Hume argued that we cannot logically derive an “ought” from an “is.”
Despite the centuries that have passed since Hume’s days, I believe that his analysis has much to teach modern surgery. Just because we can undertake many interventions for our patients, it does not follow that we should undertake all of those interventions. A central aspect of what many of us refer to commonly as “surgical judgment” is deciding among the many possible interventions for a patient, what specific ones ought we offer. Although this entire discussion may seem theoretical (and possibly even arcane) to some surgeons, I firmly believe that one of the greatest challenges to the future of surgery is whether surgeons are willing to address the question of what should be done for every patient.
Excellent surgeons have traditionally been seen as having both technical mastery and sound judgment. In the current era in which surgeons are increasingly pushed to do more cases and maximize RVUs, multiple forces are encouraging surgeons to increasingly become pure technicians. Technicians can answer the question “what can be done?” However, “what should be done for this specific patient?” is a question that only a physician can answer. In the decades to come, we must ensure that surgeons continue to engage in the harder questions of “what should be done?” so that we do not forget that “is” and “ought” are different. The mastery of surgery involves not only the technical expertise that can be applied on behalf of a patient, but also the appreciation and understanding of the patient’s values so that surgeons can make recommendations about what should be done for their patients.
Dr. Angelos is the Linda Kohler Anderson Professor of Surgery and Surgical Ethics; chief, endocrine surgery; and associate director of the MacLean Center for Clinical Medical Ethics at the University of Chicago.
Many years ago during medical school, I took time out to pursue graduate studies in philosophy. At that time, I took a number of courses that explored various approaches to the philosophical questions of morality and ethics. My ultimate goal, even back then, was to focus on ethical issues in the practice of medicine.
I often found the philosophical discussions from the “giants” in philosophy were not always easy to apply to everyday problems. After completing my graduate studies in philosophy and nearing the end of medical school, I found that I was drawn to surgery. Not surprisingly, many surgical faculty that I interviewed with for my residency saw little application of my philosophy studies to the practice of surgery. Although I felt confident that ethics was central to the practice of surgery, I let pass the general suggestions from many senior surgeons that surgery and philosophical analysis have little in common.
In recent years, however, I have increasingly seen an area of overlap that I believe will be central to the future of surgery. The options for the treatment of critically ill surgical patients across all areas of surgery have increased dramatically. Just in the area of cardiovascular disease, patients with failing hearts have the option of mechanical assist devices. Patients with multiple comorbidities and vascular problems can have numerous endovascular procedures done that years ago would have been unthinkable. Consider a patient with a ventricular assist device on a ventilator who is being dialyzed. Such a patient may be supported for weeks or months beyond what was possible just a few decades ago.
Whereas our surgical forefathers were constantly asking the question, “What can be done for this patient?” those caring for critically ill patients today must repeatedly ask, “What should we do for this patient?” Years ago, the statement, “there is nothing more that we can offer” was much more commonly heard than it is today. The critical question for today – “What should be done?” – is often more challenging and nuanced than “what can be done?” Whenever we ask “what should be done?” we must take into account the values of the patient and weigh the possible outcomes and the inherent risks of the possible interventions with the patient’s goals.
The current necessity to answer “what should be done?” has several striking parallels with the classical philosophical problem of “is” and “ought.” Over the centuries, many philosophers have considered whether we can derive an “ought” from an “is.” In other words, just because one can show that something is the case in the world, it does not automatically follow that it ought to be that way. David Hume, the Scottish philosopher (1711-1776), famously argued that there is a tremendous difference between statements about what is and statements about what ought to be. In particular, Hume argued that we cannot logically derive an “ought” from an “is.”
Despite the centuries that have passed since Hume’s days, I believe that his analysis has much to teach modern surgery. Just because we can undertake many interventions for our patients, it does not follow that we should undertake all of those interventions. A central aspect of what many of us refer to commonly as “surgical judgment” is deciding among the many possible interventions for a patient, what specific ones ought we offer. Although this entire discussion may seem theoretical (and possibly even arcane) to some surgeons, I firmly believe that one of the greatest challenges to the future of surgery is whether surgeons are willing to address the question of what should be done for every patient.
Excellent surgeons have traditionally been seen as having both technical mastery and sound judgment. In the current era in which surgeons are increasingly pushed to do more cases and maximize RVUs, multiple forces are encouraging surgeons to increasingly become pure technicians. Technicians can answer the question “what can be done?” However, “what should be done for this specific patient?” is a question that only a physician can answer. In the decades to come, we must ensure that surgeons continue to engage in the harder questions of “what should be done?” so that we do not forget that “is” and “ought” are different. The mastery of surgery involves not only the technical expertise that can be applied on behalf of a patient, but also the appreciation and understanding of the patient’s values so that surgeons can make recommendations about what should be done for their patients.
Dr. Angelos is the Linda Kohler Anderson Professor of Surgery and Surgical Ethics; chief, endocrine surgery; and associate director of the MacLean Center for Clinical Medical Ethics at the University of Chicago.
The Right Choice? When surgery is not the right choice
“A chance to cut is a chance to cure.” This common saying summarizes much of the philosophy of surgery. If we have an opportunity to do an operation and fix something, surgeons find it easy to recommend surgery. There is an immediacy about surgery and a surgical cure that is appealing to most surgeons.
As I think back to medical school, I remember that my decision to become a surgeon was greatly influenced by my subinternship in medicine. Whenever one of my patients needed an operation, I was always anxious to know what the surgeons were finding in the operating room. Having been a surgeon for many years now, I never tire of the opportunity to do something in the operating room that solves a patient’s problem. It is not surprising that when there is a surgical option for a problem, many surgeons find themselves recommending surgery. While it may be true that there is often an economic incentive for surgeons to recommend surgery, there are also many situations in which thoughtful surgeons recommend against surgery.
There are many cases in which the risks of the operation outweigh the benefits. If, for example, a patient with widely metastatic colon cancer presents for surgical evaluation, the recommendation will most commonly be against surgery. In such a case, the goal of cure or increased longevity may not be met by an operation to remove a portion of the colon when there will be a significant burden of disease that cannot be removed. In addition to cases of unresectable cancer, there are many situations in which the patient’s comorbidities make the risks of surgery far higher than the benefits. In such cases, surgeons commonly recommend against surgery or, in some cases, actually do not offer surgery as an option. Most often in such situations, the surgeon is consulted for an opinion and once surgery is deemed not to be an option, the surgeon generally steps aside to allow other doctors to provide care for the patient whether it be medical therapies, palliative care, or a combination of both.
In recent years, surgeons have increasingly been involved in nonoperative management strategies. For example, some thyroid cancer patients with small, presumed indolent cancers are entered into clinical trials where observation is one of the arms of the trial. Perhaps most well established is the recommendation that patients with early stage (Gleason 6) prostate cancer consider “active surveillance” as an option to be considered along with surgery and radiation. What is particularly notable in the case of prostate cancer is that even when the recommendation is made for active surveillance, most of these patients continue to follow up with the urologist. In this scenario, even though surgery may not have been recommended by the urologist or chosen by the patient, it is the urologist who maintains the ongoing surveillance with the patient.
In an era in which surgeons often complain about being treated purely as technicians, the role of surgeons in active surveillance should be seen as a breath of fresh air. Here, the surgeons are recommending a course of action that is much less financially beneficial than an operation. Having surgeons involved in such nonoperative strategies clearly expresses the belief that surgeons have in these approaches.
There is another important reason why surgeons should become increasingly engaged in nonoperative treatment strategies. The credibility of the recommendation to consider NOT having surgery is exponentially higher if the recommendation is made by a surgeon. Patients know that surgeons like to operate, are trained to operate, and, in many cases, are paid to operate. In this setting, the recommendation to forgo or, at least, postpone an operation is particularly influential.
There is widespread public acceptance of Abraham Maslow’s statement, “if all you have is a hammer, everything looks like a nail.” When a surgeon recommends something other than surgery it is a much stronger endorsement of the nonoperative treatment than if a nonsurgeon had made the same recommendation. Perhaps equally important is that a recommendation against surgery with ongoing engagement by the surgeon is an illustration of the surgeon’s acting in the patient’s best interests rather than in the surgeon’s best interests. Even though it may always be more difficult not to offer an operation to a patient, surgeons should not shy away from recommending nonoperative strategies when there is clear evidence that such strategies may be better for patients. Although not every patient will be comfortable with a nonoperative approach, surgeons should seek every opportunity to participate fully in such decisions when nonoperative treatments may be in the patients’ best interests.
Dr. Angelos is an ACS Fellow; the Linda Kohler Anderson Professor of Surgery and Surgical Ethics; chief, endocrine surgery; and associate director of the MacLean Center for Clinical Medical Ethics at the University of Chicago.
“A chance to cut is a chance to cure.” This common saying summarizes much of the philosophy of surgery. If we have an opportunity to do an operation and fix something, surgeons find it easy to recommend surgery. There is an immediacy about surgery and a surgical cure that is appealing to most surgeons.
As I think back to medical school, I remember that my decision to become a surgeon was greatly influenced by my subinternship in medicine. Whenever one of my patients needed an operation, I was always anxious to know what the surgeons were finding in the operating room. Having been a surgeon for many years now, I never tire of the opportunity to do something in the operating room that solves a patient’s problem. It is not surprising that when there is a surgical option for a problem, many surgeons find themselves recommending surgery. While it may be true that there is often an economic incentive for surgeons to recommend surgery, there are also many situations in which thoughtful surgeons recommend against surgery.
There are many cases in which the risks of the operation outweigh the benefits. If, for example, a patient with widely metastatic colon cancer presents for surgical evaluation, the recommendation will most commonly be against surgery. In such a case, the goal of cure or increased longevity may not be met by an operation to remove a portion of the colon when there will be a significant burden of disease that cannot be removed. In addition to cases of unresectable cancer, there are many situations in which the patient’s comorbidities make the risks of surgery far higher than the benefits. In such cases, surgeons commonly recommend against surgery or, in some cases, actually do not offer surgery as an option. Most often in such situations, the surgeon is consulted for an opinion and once surgery is deemed not to be an option, the surgeon generally steps aside to allow other doctors to provide care for the patient whether it be medical therapies, palliative care, or a combination of both.
In recent years, surgeons have increasingly been involved in nonoperative management strategies. For example, some thyroid cancer patients with small, presumed indolent cancers are entered into clinical trials where observation is one of the arms of the trial. Perhaps most well established is the recommendation that patients with early stage (Gleason 6) prostate cancer consider “active surveillance” as an option to be considered along with surgery and radiation. What is particularly notable in the case of prostate cancer is that even when the recommendation is made for active surveillance, most of these patients continue to follow up with the urologist. In this scenario, even though surgery may not have been recommended by the urologist or chosen by the patient, it is the urologist who maintains the ongoing surveillance with the patient.
In an era in which surgeons often complain about being treated purely as technicians, the role of surgeons in active surveillance should be seen as a breath of fresh air. Here, the surgeons are recommending a course of action that is much less financially beneficial than an operation. Having surgeons involved in such nonoperative strategies clearly expresses the belief that surgeons have in these approaches.
There is another important reason why surgeons should become increasingly engaged in nonoperative treatment strategies. The credibility of the recommendation to consider NOT having surgery is exponentially higher if the recommendation is made by a surgeon. Patients know that surgeons like to operate, are trained to operate, and, in many cases, are paid to operate. In this setting, the recommendation to forgo or, at least, postpone an operation is particularly influential.
There is widespread public acceptance of Abraham Maslow’s statement, “if all you have is a hammer, everything looks like a nail.” When a surgeon recommends something other than surgery it is a much stronger endorsement of the nonoperative treatment than if a nonsurgeon had made the same recommendation. Perhaps equally important is that a recommendation against surgery with ongoing engagement by the surgeon is an illustration of the surgeon’s acting in the patient’s best interests rather than in the surgeon’s best interests. Even though it may always be more difficult not to offer an operation to a patient, surgeons should not shy away from recommending nonoperative strategies when there is clear evidence that such strategies may be better for patients. Although not every patient will be comfortable with a nonoperative approach, surgeons should seek every opportunity to participate fully in such decisions when nonoperative treatments may be in the patients’ best interests.
Dr. Angelos is an ACS Fellow; the Linda Kohler Anderson Professor of Surgery and Surgical Ethics; chief, endocrine surgery; and associate director of the MacLean Center for Clinical Medical Ethics at the University of Chicago.
“A chance to cut is a chance to cure.” This common saying summarizes much of the philosophy of surgery. If we have an opportunity to do an operation and fix something, surgeons find it easy to recommend surgery. There is an immediacy about surgery and a surgical cure that is appealing to most surgeons.
As I think back to medical school, I remember that my decision to become a surgeon was greatly influenced by my subinternship in medicine. Whenever one of my patients needed an operation, I was always anxious to know what the surgeons were finding in the operating room. Having been a surgeon for many years now, I never tire of the opportunity to do something in the operating room that solves a patient’s problem. It is not surprising that when there is a surgical option for a problem, many surgeons find themselves recommending surgery. While it may be true that there is often an economic incentive for surgeons to recommend surgery, there are also many situations in which thoughtful surgeons recommend against surgery.
There are many cases in which the risks of the operation outweigh the benefits. If, for example, a patient with widely metastatic colon cancer presents for surgical evaluation, the recommendation will most commonly be against surgery. In such a case, the goal of cure or increased longevity may not be met by an operation to remove a portion of the colon when there will be a significant burden of disease that cannot be removed. In addition to cases of unresectable cancer, there are many situations in which the patient’s comorbidities make the risks of surgery far higher than the benefits. In such cases, surgeons commonly recommend against surgery or, in some cases, actually do not offer surgery as an option. Most often in such situations, the surgeon is consulted for an opinion and once surgery is deemed not to be an option, the surgeon generally steps aside to allow other doctors to provide care for the patient whether it be medical therapies, palliative care, or a combination of both.
In recent years, surgeons have increasingly been involved in nonoperative management strategies. For example, some thyroid cancer patients with small, presumed indolent cancers are entered into clinical trials where observation is one of the arms of the trial. Perhaps most well established is the recommendation that patients with early stage (Gleason 6) prostate cancer consider “active surveillance” as an option to be considered along with surgery and radiation. What is particularly notable in the case of prostate cancer is that even when the recommendation is made for active surveillance, most of these patients continue to follow up with the urologist. In this scenario, even though surgery may not have been recommended by the urologist or chosen by the patient, it is the urologist who maintains the ongoing surveillance with the patient.
In an era in which surgeons often complain about being treated purely as technicians, the role of surgeons in active surveillance should be seen as a breath of fresh air. Here, the surgeons are recommending a course of action that is much less financially beneficial than an operation. Having surgeons involved in such nonoperative strategies clearly expresses the belief that surgeons have in these approaches.
There is another important reason why surgeons should become increasingly engaged in nonoperative treatment strategies. The credibility of the recommendation to consider NOT having surgery is exponentially higher if the recommendation is made by a surgeon. Patients know that surgeons like to operate, are trained to operate, and, in many cases, are paid to operate. In this setting, the recommendation to forgo or, at least, postpone an operation is particularly influential.
There is widespread public acceptance of Abraham Maslow’s statement, “if all you have is a hammer, everything looks like a nail.” When a surgeon recommends something other than surgery it is a much stronger endorsement of the nonoperative treatment than if a nonsurgeon had made the same recommendation. Perhaps equally important is that a recommendation against surgery with ongoing engagement by the surgeon is an illustration of the surgeon’s acting in the patient’s best interests rather than in the surgeon’s best interests. Even though it may always be more difficult not to offer an operation to a patient, surgeons should not shy away from recommending nonoperative strategies when there is clear evidence that such strategies may be better for patients. Although not every patient will be comfortable with a nonoperative approach, surgeons should seek every opportunity to participate fully in such decisions when nonoperative treatments may be in the patients’ best interests.
Dr. Angelos is an ACS Fellow; the Linda Kohler Anderson Professor of Surgery and Surgical Ethics; chief, endocrine surgery; and associate director of the MacLean Center for Clinical Medical Ethics at the University of Chicago.
The Right Choice? Kindness and Surgical Ethics: Reflections on a Friend and Mentor
As I sit down to write this column, I reflect on the news that my mentor and friend, Norman W. Thompson, M.D, FACS, passed away yesterday. I had the good fortune to spend 1 year as an endocrine surgery fellow with Dr. Thompson at the University of Michigan in 1995-96. That year was certainly the most significant of my training in terms of defining my professional life as an endocrine surgeon. However, as I think back on my time with Dr. Thompson, I am struck by how much more I learned from him than how to take out a thyroid or a parathyroid or manage multiple endocrine neoplasia.
Dr. Thompson was an excellent technical surgeon, and he would have had a tremendous career helping thousands of patients if that was all that he had done. However, he was much more than an excellent technician. He was also a great doctor. In order for a surgeon to be a great doctor, it is necessary to be technically excellent, but that alone is not sufficient. I believe that what makes a surgeon a great doctor is the combination of technical mastery with outstanding interpersonal skills and ethically sound clinical judgment. Dr. Thompson had all of that, and he was exceptionally kind.
Kindness is not a word that we commonly use in describing surgeons today. In an era of surgeons being pressured to see more patients and generate more RVUs [relative value units], it is unusual to hear kindness mentioned as an essential attribute of a great surgeon. However, Dr. Thompson’s kindness was immediately apparent to all who spent time with him. He treated each patient as a unique individual. In addition, he treated his trainees and his colleagues in Ann Arbor and around the world with respect and incredible humility. He was generous with his time and was always approachable no matter how inexperienced the surgeon asking him a question. Dr. Thompson was kind to all of us and made us feel that he valued spending time with us.
What does kindness have to do with a column that traditionally focuses on ethical issues in the practice of surgery? Although acting with kindness is not the same as acting in an ethical manner, I believe that there is more overlap of the terms than we often imagine. The kind surgeon is the one who treats people – whether they are patients or colleagues – as though they matter. The ethical surgeon respects the patient’s wishes and acts to benefit the patient as much as possible in all circumstances. I am certain that I have met ethical surgeons who were not kind, but I have met very few kind surgeons who are not ethical.
As someone who has spent significant time and energy in the last 19 years as a surgery faculty member trying to teach ethics, I am also struck by a clear truth. Actions always speak louder than words. It may be valuable to talk about the ethical principles that may come to play in a particularly difficult surgical case. Defining the competing interests and assessing the patient’s wishes are important components of the ethical practice of surgery. However, no amount of discussion of these issues can substitute for the value of behavior. Treating patients and colleagues with kindness and respect is modeling the behaviors of an ethical surgeon – perhaps learned from a wise and thoughtful mentor.
Dr. Thompson was an excellent role model for me and so many others in how he treated patients and everyone around him. As I see patients and perform surgery, I still hear myself saying many of the same things that he said many years ago. His genuine expressions of optimism before difficult operations, honesty in communicating, and sadness when things did not go well were tremendous examples to me of how a great doctor treats those around him. These lessons that I learned from Dr. Thompson have influenced my practice significantly, and I am grateful for the opportunity to try to model them on a daily basis.
Although I remain convinced that formal curricula in ethics and professionalism remain important in the education of today’s surgeons, it is valuable to remember the impact that the behaviors of those we respect have on us. Perhaps we surgeons more than other physicians are molded by the people who train us, but there is no question that the ethical behaviors of our teachers and mentors will have a greater impact than any lecture or manuscript. I want to acknowledge and commemorate the kindness and ethical behaviors that Dr. Thompson modeled daily for all who were fortunate enough to work with him.
Dr. Angelos is an ACS Fellow; the Linda Kohler Anderson Professor of Surgery and Surgical Ethics; chief, endocrine surgery; and associate director of the MacLean Center for Clinical Medical Ethics at the University of Chicago.
As I sit down to write this column, I reflect on the news that my mentor and friend, Norman W. Thompson, M.D, FACS, passed away yesterday. I had the good fortune to spend 1 year as an endocrine surgery fellow with Dr. Thompson at the University of Michigan in 1995-96. That year was certainly the most significant of my training in terms of defining my professional life as an endocrine surgeon. However, as I think back on my time with Dr. Thompson, I am struck by how much more I learned from him than how to take out a thyroid or a parathyroid or manage multiple endocrine neoplasia.
Dr. Thompson was an excellent technical surgeon, and he would have had a tremendous career helping thousands of patients if that was all that he had done. However, he was much more than an excellent technician. He was also a great doctor. In order for a surgeon to be a great doctor, it is necessary to be technically excellent, but that alone is not sufficient. I believe that what makes a surgeon a great doctor is the combination of technical mastery with outstanding interpersonal skills and ethically sound clinical judgment. Dr. Thompson had all of that, and he was exceptionally kind.
Kindness is not a word that we commonly use in describing surgeons today. In an era of surgeons being pressured to see more patients and generate more RVUs [relative value units], it is unusual to hear kindness mentioned as an essential attribute of a great surgeon. However, Dr. Thompson’s kindness was immediately apparent to all who spent time with him. He treated each patient as a unique individual. In addition, he treated his trainees and his colleagues in Ann Arbor and around the world with respect and incredible humility. He was generous with his time and was always approachable no matter how inexperienced the surgeon asking him a question. Dr. Thompson was kind to all of us and made us feel that he valued spending time with us.
What does kindness have to do with a column that traditionally focuses on ethical issues in the practice of surgery? Although acting with kindness is not the same as acting in an ethical manner, I believe that there is more overlap of the terms than we often imagine. The kind surgeon is the one who treats people – whether they are patients or colleagues – as though they matter. The ethical surgeon respects the patient’s wishes and acts to benefit the patient as much as possible in all circumstances. I am certain that I have met ethical surgeons who were not kind, but I have met very few kind surgeons who are not ethical.
As someone who has spent significant time and energy in the last 19 years as a surgery faculty member trying to teach ethics, I am also struck by a clear truth. Actions always speak louder than words. It may be valuable to talk about the ethical principles that may come to play in a particularly difficult surgical case. Defining the competing interests and assessing the patient’s wishes are important components of the ethical practice of surgery. However, no amount of discussion of these issues can substitute for the value of behavior. Treating patients and colleagues with kindness and respect is modeling the behaviors of an ethical surgeon – perhaps learned from a wise and thoughtful mentor.
Dr. Thompson was an excellent role model for me and so many others in how he treated patients and everyone around him. As I see patients and perform surgery, I still hear myself saying many of the same things that he said many years ago. His genuine expressions of optimism before difficult operations, honesty in communicating, and sadness when things did not go well were tremendous examples to me of how a great doctor treats those around him. These lessons that I learned from Dr. Thompson have influenced my practice significantly, and I am grateful for the opportunity to try to model them on a daily basis.
Although I remain convinced that formal curricula in ethics and professionalism remain important in the education of today’s surgeons, it is valuable to remember the impact that the behaviors of those we respect have on us. Perhaps we surgeons more than other physicians are molded by the people who train us, but there is no question that the ethical behaviors of our teachers and mentors will have a greater impact than any lecture or manuscript. I want to acknowledge and commemorate the kindness and ethical behaviors that Dr. Thompson modeled daily for all who were fortunate enough to work with him.
Dr. Angelos is an ACS Fellow; the Linda Kohler Anderson Professor of Surgery and Surgical Ethics; chief, endocrine surgery; and associate director of the MacLean Center for Clinical Medical Ethics at the University of Chicago.
As I sit down to write this column, I reflect on the news that my mentor and friend, Norman W. Thompson, M.D, FACS, passed away yesterday. I had the good fortune to spend 1 year as an endocrine surgery fellow with Dr. Thompson at the University of Michigan in 1995-96. That year was certainly the most significant of my training in terms of defining my professional life as an endocrine surgeon. However, as I think back on my time with Dr. Thompson, I am struck by how much more I learned from him than how to take out a thyroid or a parathyroid or manage multiple endocrine neoplasia.
Dr. Thompson was an excellent technical surgeon, and he would have had a tremendous career helping thousands of patients if that was all that he had done. However, he was much more than an excellent technician. He was also a great doctor. In order for a surgeon to be a great doctor, it is necessary to be technically excellent, but that alone is not sufficient. I believe that what makes a surgeon a great doctor is the combination of technical mastery with outstanding interpersonal skills and ethically sound clinical judgment. Dr. Thompson had all of that, and he was exceptionally kind.
Kindness is not a word that we commonly use in describing surgeons today. In an era of surgeons being pressured to see more patients and generate more RVUs [relative value units], it is unusual to hear kindness mentioned as an essential attribute of a great surgeon. However, Dr. Thompson’s kindness was immediately apparent to all who spent time with him. He treated each patient as a unique individual. In addition, he treated his trainees and his colleagues in Ann Arbor and around the world with respect and incredible humility. He was generous with his time and was always approachable no matter how inexperienced the surgeon asking him a question. Dr. Thompson was kind to all of us and made us feel that he valued spending time with us.
What does kindness have to do with a column that traditionally focuses on ethical issues in the practice of surgery? Although acting with kindness is not the same as acting in an ethical manner, I believe that there is more overlap of the terms than we often imagine. The kind surgeon is the one who treats people – whether they are patients or colleagues – as though they matter. The ethical surgeon respects the patient’s wishes and acts to benefit the patient as much as possible in all circumstances. I am certain that I have met ethical surgeons who were not kind, but I have met very few kind surgeons who are not ethical.
As someone who has spent significant time and energy in the last 19 years as a surgery faculty member trying to teach ethics, I am also struck by a clear truth. Actions always speak louder than words. It may be valuable to talk about the ethical principles that may come to play in a particularly difficult surgical case. Defining the competing interests and assessing the patient’s wishes are important components of the ethical practice of surgery. However, no amount of discussion of these issues can substitute for the value of behavior. Treating patients and colleagues with kindness and respect is modeling the behaviors of an ethical surgeon – perhaps learned from a wise and thoughtful mentor.
Dr. Thompson was an excellent role model for me and so many others in how he treated patients and everyone around him. As I see patients and perform surgery, I still hear myself saying many of the same things that he said many years ago. His genuine expressions of optimism before difficult operations, honesty in communicating, and sadness when things did not go well were tremendous examples to me of how a great doctor treats those around him. These lessons that I learned from Dr. Thompson have influenced my practice significantly, and I am grateful for the opportunity to try to model them on a daily basis.
Although I remain convinced that formal curricula in ethics and professionalism remain important in the education of today’s surgeons, it is valuable to remember the impact that the behaviors of those we respect have on us. Perhaps we surgeons more than other physicians are molded by the people who train us, but there is no question that the ethical behaviors of our teachers and mentors will have a greater impact than any lecture or manuscript. I want to acknowledge and commemorate the kindness and ethical behaviors that Dr. Thompson modeled daily for all who were fortunate enough to work with him.
Dr. Angelos is an ACS Fellow; the Linda Kohler Anderson Professor of Surgery and Surgical Ethics; chief, endocrine surgery; and associate director of the MacLean Center for Clinical Medical Ethics at the University of Chicago.
The Right Choice? The importance of sometimes saying “no”
When I was a resident, one of the surgery faculty who often performed big, high-risk operations liked to say, “If the patient can tolerate a haircut, he can tolerate an operation.” By this, he meant that there were not patients who were too sick for surgery if the operation was indicated. However, over the last 2 decades, I have seen a handful of patients for whom the risks of the operation far outweigh the potential benefits and for whom I have said I am not offering surgery as an option.
Recently, I had a chance to discuss troubling ethics cases with group of thoughtful surgical residents. They raised concerns over the common scenario of being consulted in the middle of the night on the critically ill patient in the intensive care unit for whom the risks of surgery are extremely high. These residents asked the question of whether it is ever acceptable for surgeons to simply refuse to take such patients to the operating room if the alternative to surgery is virtually certain death. The overriding concern among the residents was whether saying “no” to a request for operative intervention in a critically ill patient can ever be justified since the surgeon is essentially “playing God” by not offering the possibility of intervention.
There is no question that there can be very sick patients who have a poor prognosis and the decision is appropriately made to recommend surgery even though the risks are very high. I also believe that there are patients for whom the risks of surgery are so high, and the prospects for a good outcome are so low, that surgery should not be recommended. However, it is important to distinguish two different scenarios. In one scenario, the surgical consultant decides that surgery is an option, but then tries to convince the surrogate decision makers (usually the patient’s family) to decline surgery because of the very high risks. In the second scenario, the surgeon decides that the risks to the patient are so high that it would be wrong to even take the patient to the operating room.
In both scenarios, the patient does not get an operation and in the vast majority of such cases, the patient will die in a short period of time. The question remains whether it is better to give families a choice or not. I believe that posing the question in this manner is misleading and presents a false dichotomy.
Although the distinctions can be subtle, it is critical for the surgeon to decide whether each patient has a high enough chance for survival that the operation is medically justifiable. If the answer is “yes,” then the next question will be one for the surrogate decision makers to decide whether to consent to the surgery or not. Based on the importance of respecting the autonomous choices of patients or their surrogates, it is important that surgeons respect the choice not to have an operation even if one is being recommended. If the answer to the question of whether the operation is medically justifiable is “no,” to offer surgery to family and then try to convince them to decline it by overstating the risks is misleading. Although such a strategy would give the family a sense of control over the situation, it would also give the false impression that surgery is truly an option. To act this way would allow the surgeon the ability to avoid “playing God” since the family is “making the decision”. However, I believe that taking that decision away from families when there is not really a reasonable choice for surgery is a better way to eliminate their potential guilt. Not only is it ethically acceptable to decline to offer an operation to an extremely high-risk patient, I would argue that such behavior is actually the ethical responsibility of the surgeon. We should take on the burden of saying “no” when surgery should NOT be performed. Forcing such a decision on families in the name of respecting autonomy is to shirk our responsibility and something that we must avoid doing whenever possible.
Dr. Angelos is an ACS Fellow; the Linda Kohler Anderson Professor of Surgery and Surgical Ethics; chief, endocrine surgery; and associate director of the MacLean Center for Clinical Medical Ethics at the University of Chicago.
When I was a resident, one of the surgery faculty who often performed big, high-risk operations liked to say, “If the patient can tolerate a haircut, he can tolerate an operation.” By this, he meant that there were not patients who were too sick for surgery if the operation was indicated. However, over the last 2 decades, I have seen a handful of patients for whom the risks of the operation far outweigh the potential benefits and for whom I have said I am not offering surgery as an option.
Recently, I had a chance to discuss troubling ethics cases with group of thoughtful surgical residents. They raised concerns over the common scenario of being consulted in the middle of the night on the critically ill patient in the intensive care unit for whom the risks of surgery are extremely high. These residents asked the question of whether it is ever acceptable for surgeons to simply refuse to take such patients to the operating room if the alternative to surgery is virtually certain death. The overriding concern among the residents was whether saying “no” to a request for operative intervention in a critically ill patient can ever be justified since the surgeon is essentially “playing God” by not offering the possibility of intervention.
There is no question that there can be very sick patients who have a poor prognosis and the decision is appropriately made to recommend surgery even though the risks are very high. I also believe that there are patients for whom the risks of surgery are so high, and the prospects for a good outcome are so low, that surgery should not be recommended. However, it is important to distinguish two different scenarios. In one scenario, the surgical consultant decides that surgery is an option, but then tries to convince the surrogate decision makers (usually the patient’s family) to decline surgery because of the very high risks. In the second scenario, the surgeon decides that the risks to the patient are so high that it would be wrong to even take the patient to the operating room.
In both scenarios, the patient does not get an operation and in the vast majority of such cases, the patient will die in a short period of time. The question remains whether it is better to give families a choice or not. I believe that posing the question in this manner is misleading and presents a false dichotomy.
Although the distinctions can be subtle, it is critical for the surgeon to decide whether each patient has a high enough chance for survival that the operation is medically justifiable. If the answer is “yes,” then the next question will be one for the surrogate decision makers to decide whether to consent to the surgery or not. Based on the importance of respecting the autonomous choices of patients or their surrogates, it is important that surgeons respect the choice not to have an operation even if one is being recommended. If the answer to the question of whether the operation is medically justifiable is “no,” to offer surgery to family and then try to convince them to decline it by overstating the risks is misleading. Although such a strategy would give the family a sense of control over the situation, it would also give the false impression that surgery is truly an option. To act this way would allow the surgeon the ability to avoid “playing God” since the family is “making the decision”. However, I believe that taking that decision away from families when there is not really a reasonable choice for surgery is a better way to eliminate their potential guilt. Not only is it ethically acceptable to decline to offer an operation to an extremely high-risk patient, I would argue that such behavior is actually the ethical responsibility of the surgeon. We should take on the burden of saying “no” when surgery should NOT be performed. Forcing such a decision on families in the name of respecting autonomy is to shirk our responsibility and something that we must avoid doing whenever possible.
Dr. Angelos is an ACS Fellow; the Linda Kohler Anderson Professor of Surgery and Surgical Ethics; chief, endocrine surgery; and associate director of the MacLean Center for Clinical Medical Ethics at the University of Chicago.
When I was a resident, one of the surgery faculty who often performed big, high-risk operations liked to say, “If the patient can tolerate a haircut, he can tolerate an operation.” By this, he meant that there were not patients who were too sick for surgery if the operation was indicated. However, over the last 2 decades, I have seen a handful of patients for whom the risks of the operation far outweigh the potential benefits and for whom I have said I am not offering surgery as an option.
Recently, I had a chance to discuss troubling ethics cases with group of thoughtful surgical residents. They raised concerns over the common scenario of being consulted in the middle of the night on the critically ill patient in the intensive care unit for whom the risks of surgery are extremely high. These residents asked the question of whether it is ever acceptable for surgeons to simply refuse to take such patients to the operating room if the alternative to surgery is virtually certain death. The overriding concern among the residents was whether saying “no” to a request for operative intervention in a critically ill patient can ever be justified since the surgeon is essentially “playing God” by not offering the possibility of intervention.
There is no question that there can be very sick patients who have a poor prognosis and the decision is appropriately made to recommend surgery even though the risks are very high. I also believe that there are patients for whom the risks of surgery are so high, and the prospects for a good outcome are so low, that surgery should not be recommended. However, it is important to distinguish two different scenarios. In one scenario, the surgical consultant decides that surgery is an option, but then tries to convince the surrogate decision makers (usually the patient’s family) to decline surgery because of the very high risks. In the second scenario, the surgeon decides that the risks to the patient are so high that it would be wrong to even take the patient to the operating room.
In both scenarios, the patient does not get an operation and in the vast majority of such cases, the patient will die in a short period of time. The question remains whether it is better to give families a choice or not. I believe that posing the question in this manner is misleading and presents a false dichotomy.
Although the distinctions can be subtle, it is critical for the surgeon to decide whether each patient has a high enough chance for survival that the operation is medically justifiable. If the answer is “yes,” then the next question will be one for the surrogate decision makers to decide whether to consent to the surgery or not. Based on the importance of respecting the autonomous choices of patients or their surrogates, it is important that surgeons respect the choice not to have an operation even if one is being recommended. If the answer to the question of whether the operation is medically justifiable is “no,” to offer surgery to family and then try to convince them to decline it by overstating the risks is misleading. Although such a strategy would give the family a sense of control over the situation, it would also give the false impression that surgery is truly an option. To act this way would allow the surgeon the ability to avoid “playing God” since the family is “making the decision”. However, I believe that taking that decision away from families when there is not really a reasonable choice for surgery is a better way to eliminate their potential guilt. Not only is it ethically acceptable to decline to offer an operation to an extremely high-risk patient, I would argue that such behavior is actually the ethical responsibility of the surgeon. We should take on the burden of saying “no” when surgery should NOT be performed. Forcing such a decision on families in the name of respecting autonomy is to shirk our responsibility and something that we must avoid doing whenever possible.
Dr. Angelos is an ACS Fellow; the Linda Kohler Anderson Professor of Surgery and Surgical Ethics; chief, endocrine surgery; and associate director of the MacLean Center for Clinical Medical Ethics at the University of Chicago.