The ethics of ICDs: History and future directions

Article Type
Changed
Tue, 08/15/2017 - 15:22
Display Headline
The ethics of ICDs: History and future directions

In 1975, Julia and Joseph Quinlan approached the administrator of St. Clare’s Hospital in Denville, New Jersey, and requested that the mechanical ventilator on which their adopted daughter, Karen, was dependent be turned off. Karen Ann Quinlan, 21 years old, was in a permanent vegetative state after a severe anoxic event, and her parents had been informed by the hospital’s medical staff that she would never regain consciousness.

See related article

To the Quinlans’ request to withdraw the ventilator, the hospital administrator replied, “You have to understand our position, Mrs. Quinlan. In this hospital we don’t kill people.”1

The administrator’s response was consistent with prevailing ethical and legal perspectives, analyses, and directives at that time related to discontinuation of life-sustaining treatment. In the mid-1970s, the American Medical Association’s position was that it was permissible to not put a patient on a ventilator (ie, a physician could withhold a life-sustaining treatment), but once a patient was on a ventilator, it was not permissible to take the patient off if the intention was to allow death to occur.1 However, the New Jersey Supreme Court ultimately found this distinction between withholding and withdrawing unconvincing, and ruled unanimously that Karen Quinlan’s ventilator could be turned off.2

THE HASTINGS CENTER REPORT: STOPPING IS THE SAME AS NOT STARTING

During the subsequent decade, further ethical analysis and additional legal cases resulted in new insights and more nuanced thinking about forgoing life-sustaining treatment.

These developments were summarized in a 1987 report by the Hastings Center,3 a leading bioethics research and policy institute. The report provided normative guidance for the termination of life-sustaining treatment and for the care of dying patients. It acknowledged that deciding not to start a life-sustaining treatment can emotionally and psychologically affect healthcare professionals differently than deciding to stop such a treatment. However, the report also asserted that there is no morally important difference between withholding and withdrawing such treatments.

There is no ethical requirement that treatment, once started, must continue against the patient’s wishes

Reflecting a partnership model between patients and professionals for healthcare decision-making, and affirming the ethical significance of both a burden-benefit analysis and patient autonomy, the report stated that when a patient or surrogate in collaboration with a responsible healthcare professional decides that a treatment under way and the life it supports have become more burdensome than beneficial to the patient, that is sufficient reason to stop. There is no ethical requirement that treatment, once initiated, must continue against the patient’s wishes or when the surrogate determines that it is more burdensome than beneficial from the patient’s perspective. In fact, imposing treatment in such circumstances violates the patient’s right to self-determination.3

The report noted further that, because of frequent uncertainty about the efficacy of proposed treatments, it is preferable to initiate time-limited trials of treatments and then later stop them if they prove ineffective or become overly burdensome from a patient’s perspective.

ICDs ARE LIKE OTHER LIFE-SUSTAINING THERAPIES

In this issue of Cleveland Clinic Journal of Medicine, Baibars et al4 address the question of how implantable cardioverter-defibrillators (ICDs) should be managed at the end of life. The historical events and developments recounted above regarding withdrawing life-sustaining technologies are an appropriate context for ethically assessing the management of ICDs for dying patients.

ICDs are not ventilators, but like ventilators, they are a life-sustaining therapy

Obviously, ICDs are not ventilators, but like ventilators, they are life-sustaining therapy, as are dialysis machines, blood transfusions, medically supplied nutrition and hydration, ventricular assist devices, and other implantable electronic cardiac devices such as pacemakers. Each of these life-sustaining therapies, depending on a patient’s clinical condition, underlying illness, and comorbidities, can become a death-prolonging technology.

An ethical framework and analysis about whether to continue any life-sustaining therapy, including an ICD, must include an assessment of the benefit-to-burden ratio from the patient’s perspective. Does the therapy enhance or maintain a quality of life acceptable to the patient? Or has it become overly burdensome and does it maintain a quality of life the patient finds (or would find) unacceptable? If the latter is true, and especially in the context of an underlying terminal condition, then shifting the goals of care to focus on comfort is always appropriate and ethically justified. Treatments—including ICDs—that do not contribute to patient comfort should be withdrawn.

TOWARD COMPETENCY IN ETHICAL MANAGEMENT

Baibars et al note that much more needs to be done to enhance competencies, increase proficiencies, and mitigate the moral distress of healthcare professionals caring for dying patients with ICDs and other devices. To help clinicians achieve a personal and professional “comfort zone” for ethically managing patients with ICDs, we recommend that healthcare institutions, medical schools, and nursing schools take the following steps:

Develop comprehensive end-of-life policies, procedures, and protocols that incorporate specific guidance for managing cardiac devices and that have been endorsed by a hospital ethics committee. Such guidance can be informative and educational and can ensure that decisions and resulting actions (including stopping cardiac devices) are ethically supportable.

Provide more palliative care training in medical and nursing schools, residency programs, and continuing education activities so that front-line clinicians can deliver “basic,” “primary” palliative care not requiring specialty palliative medicine. This training, called for in the Institute of Medicine’s 2014 report, Dying in America,5 should include explicit ethics discussions about managing cardiac devices at the end of life.

Provide ongoing training in communication skills needed for all patient-professional encounters. Effectively engaging patients in goals-of-care discussions, especially patients with life-limiting illnesses such as heart failure, cannot be achieved without these skills.

References
  1. Pence G. Comas: Karen Quinlan and Nancy Cruzan. In: Classic Cases in Medical Ethics: Accounts of Cases That Have Shaped Medical Ethics, With Philosophical, Legal, and Historical Backgrounds, 3rd edition. Boston: McGraw-Hill; 2000:29–55.
  2. In the matter of Karen Quinlan, an alleged incompetent. In re Quinlan. 70 N.J. 10, 355 A.2d 647 (1976), cert. denied, 429 U.S. 922 (1976).
  3. Wolf SM. Hastings Center. Guidelines on the Termination of Life-Sustaining Treatment and Care of the Dying: A Report by the Hastings Center. The Hastings Center: Briarcliff Manor, NY; 1987.
  4. Baibars MM, Alraies MC, Kabach A, Pritzker M. Can patients opt to turn off implantable cardioverter-defibrillators near the end of life? Cleve Clin J Med 2016; 83:97–98.
  5. National Academy of Sciences. Dying in America: improving quality and honoring individual p near the end of life. www.iom.edu/Reports/2014/Dying-In-America-Improving-Quality-and-Honoring-Individual-P-Near-the-End-of-Life.aspx. Accessed January 4, 2016.
Article PDF
Author and Disclosure Information

Martin L. Smith, STD
Associate Director, Center for Ethics, Humanities, and Spiritual Care, and Director of Clinical Ethics, Department of Bioethics, Cleveland Clinic

Eric Kodish, MD
Director, Center for Ethics, Humanities, and Spiritual Care, and Professor of Pediatrics, Cleveland Clinic Lerner College of Medicine of Case Western Reserve University, Cleveland, OH

Address: Martin L. Smith, STD, Center for Ethics, Humanities, and Spiritual Care, JJ60, Cleveland Clinic, 9500 Euclid Avenue, Cleveland, OH 44195; e-mail: [email protected]

Dr. Kodish has disclosed consulting for Biogen.

Issue
Cleveland Clinic Journal of Medicine - 83(2)
Publications
Topics
Page Number
99-100
Legacy Keywords
implantable cardioverter-defibrillator, ICD, end of life, cardiac implantable electronic device, CIED, withdrawing therapy, Karen Ann Quinlan, Hastings Center, life-sustaining therapy, hospice, Martin Smith, Eric Kodish
Sections
Author and Disclosure Information

Martin L. Smith, STD
Associate Director, Center for Ethics, Humanities, and Spiritual Care, and Director of Clinical Ethics, Department of Bioethics, Cleveland Clinic

Eric Kodish, MD
Director, Center for Ethics, Humanities, and Spiritual Care, and Professor of Pediatrics, Cleveland Clinic Lerner College of Medicine of Case Western Reserve University, Cleveland, OH

Address: Martin L. Smith, STD, Center for Ethics, Humanities, and Spiritual Care, JJ60, Cleveland Clinic, 9500 Euclid Avenue, Cleveland, OH 44195; e-mail: [email protected]

Dr. Kodish has disclosed consulting for Biogen.

Author and Disclosure Information

Martin L. Smith, STD
Associate Director, Center for Ethics, Humanities, and Spiritual Care, and Director of Clinical Ethics, Department of Bioethics, Cleveland Clinic

Eric Kodish, MD
Director, Center for Ethics, Humanities, and Spiritual Care, and Professor of Pediatrics, Cleveland Clinic Lerner College of Medicine of Case Western Reserve University, Cleveland, OH

Address: Martin L. Smith, STD, Center for Ethics, Humanities, and Spiritual Care, JJ60, Cleveland Clinic, 9500 Euclid Avenue, Cleveland, OH 44195; e-mail: [email protected]

Dr. Kodish has disclosed consulting for Biogen.

Article PDF
Article PDF
Related Articles

In 1975, Julia and Joseph Quinlan approached the administrator of St. Clare’s Hospital in Denville, New Jersey, and requested that the mechanical ventilator on which their adopted daughter, Karen, was dependent be turned off. Karen Ann Quinlan, 21 years old, was in a permanent vegetative state after a severe anoxic event, and her parents had been informed by the hospital’s medical staff that she would never regain consciousness.

See related article

To the Quinlans’ request to withdraw the ventilator, the hospital administrator replied, “You have to understand our position, Mrs. Quinlan. In this hospital we don’t kill people.”1

The administrator’s response was consistent with prevailing ethical and legal perspectives, analyses, and directives at that time related to discontinuation of life-sustaining treatment. In the mid-1970s, the American Medical Association’s position was that it was permissible to not put a patient on a ventilator (ie, a physician could withhold a life-sustaining treatment), but once a patient was on a ventilator, it was not permissible to take the patient off if the intention was to allow death to occur.1 However, the New Jersey Supreme Court ultimately found this distinction between withholding and withdrawing unconvincing, and ruled unanimously that Karen Quinlan’s ventilator could be turned off.2

THE HASTINGS CENTER REPORT: STOPPING IS THE SAME AS NOT STARTING

During the subsequent decade, further ethical analysis and additional legal cases resulted in new insights and more nuanced thinking about forgoing life-sustaining treatment.

These developments were summarized in a 1987 report by the Hastings Center,3 a leading bioethics research and policy institute. The report provided normative guidance for the termination of life-sustaining treatment and for the care of dying patients. It acknowledged that deciding not to start a life-sustaining treatment can emotionally and psychologically affect healthcare professionals differently than deciding to stop such a treatment. However, the report also asserted that there is no morally important difference between withholding and withdrawing such treatments.

There is no ethical requirement that treatment, once started, must continue against the patient’s wishes

Reflecting a partnership model between patients and professionals for healthcare decision-making, and affirming the ethical significance of both a burden-benefit analysis and patient autonomy, the report stated that when a patient or surrogate in collaboration with a responsible healthcare professional decides that a treatment under way and the life it supports have become more burdensome than beneficial to the patient, that is sufficient reason to stop. There is no ethical requirement that treatment, once initiated, must continue against the patient’s wishes or when the surrogate determines that it is more burdensome than beneficial from the patient’s perspective. In fact, imposing treatment in such circumstances violates the patient’s right to self-determination.3

The report noted further that, because of frequent uncertainty about the efficacy of proposed treatments, it is preferable to initiate time-limited trials of treatments and then later stop them if they prove ineffective or become overly burdensome from a patient’s perspective.

ICDs ARE LIKE OTHER LIFE-SUSTAINING THERAPIES

In this issue of Cleveland Clinic Journal of Medicine, Baibars et al4 address the question of how implantable cardioverter-defibrillators (ICDs) should be managed at the end of life. The historical events and developments recounted above regarding withdrawing life-sustaining technologies are an appropriate context for ethically assessing the management of ICDs for dying patients.

ICDs are not ventilators, but like ventilators, they are a life-sustaining therapy

Obviously, ICDs are not ventilators, but like ventilators, they are life-sustaining therapy, as are dialysis machines, blood transfusions, medically supplied nutrition and hydration, ventricular assist devices, and other implantable electronic cardiac devices such as pacemakers. Each of these life-sustaining therapies, depending on a patient’s clinical condition, underlying illness, and comorbidities, can become a death-prolonging technology.

An ethical framework and analysis about whether to continue any life-sustaining therapy, including an ICD, must include an assessment of the benefit-to-burden ratio from the patient’s perspective. Does the therapy enhance or maintain a quality of life acceptable to the patient? Or has it become overly burdensome and does it maintain a quality of life the patient finds (or would find) unacceptable? If the latter is true, and especially in the context of an underlying terminal condition, then shifting the goals of care to focus on comfort is always appropriate and ethically justified. Treatments—including ICDs—that do not contribute to patient comfort should be withdrawn.

TOWARD COMPETENCY IN ETHICAL MANAGEMENT

Baibars et al note that much more needs to be done to enhance competencies, increase proficiencies, and mitigate the moral distress of healthcare professionals caring for dying patients with ICDs and other devices. To help clinicians achieve a personal and professional “comfort zone” for ethically managing patients with ICDs, we recommend that healthcare institutions, medical schools, and nursing schools take the following steps:

Develop comprehensive end-of-life policies, procedures, and protocols that incorporate specific guidance for managing cardiac devices and that have been endorsed by a hospital ethics committee. Such guidance can be informative and educational and can ensure that decisions and resulting actions (including stopping cardiac devices) are ethically supportable.

Provide more palliative care training in medical and nursing schools, residency programs, and continuing education activities so that front-line clinicians can deliver “basic,” “primary” palliative care not requiring specialty palliative medicine. This training, called for in the Institute of Medicine’s 2014 report, Dying in America,5 should include explicit ethics discussions about managing cardiac devices at the end of life.

Provide ongoing training in communication skills needed for all patient-professional encounters. Effectively engaging patients in goals-of-care discussions, especially patients with life-limiting illnesses such as heart failure, cannot be achieved without these skills.

In 1975, Julia and Joseph Quinlan approached the administrator of St. Clare’s Hospital in Denville, New Jersey, and requested that the mechanical ventilator on which their adopted daughter, Karen, was dependent be turned off. Karen Ann Quinlan, 21 years old, was in a permanent vegetative state after a severe anoxic event, and her parents had been informed by the hospital’s medical staff that she would never regain consciousness.

See related article

To the Quinlans’ request to withdraw the ventilator, the hospital administrator replied, “You have to understand our position, Mrs. Quinlan. In this hospital we don’t kill people.”1

The administrator’s response was consistent with prevailing ethical and legal perspectives, analyses, and directives at that time related to discontinuation of life-sustaining treatment. In the mid-1970s, the American Medical Association’s position was that it was permissible to not put a patient on a ventilator (ie, a physician could withhold a life-sustaining treatment), but once a patient was on a ventilator, it was not permissible to take the patient off if the intention was to allow death to occur.1 However, the New Jersey Supreme Court ultimately found this distinction between withholding and withdrawing unconvincing, and ruled unanimously that Karen Quinlan’s ventilator could be turned off.2

THE HASTINGS CENTER REPORT: STOPPING IS THE SAME AS NOT STARTING

During the subsequent decade, further ethical analysis and additional legal cases resulted in new insights and more nuanced thinking about forgoing life-sustaining treatment.

These developments were summarized in a 1987 report by the Hastings Center,3 a leading bioethics research and policy institute. The report provided normative guidance for the termination of life-sustaining treatment and for the care of dying patients. It acknowledged that deciding not to start a life-sustaining treatment can emotionally and psychologically affect healthcare professionals differently than deciding to stop such a treatment. However, the report also asserted that there is no morally important difference between withholding and withdrawing such treatments.

There is no ethical requirement that treatment, once started, must continue against the patient’s wishes

Reflecting a partnership model between patients and professionals for healthcare decision-making, and affirming the ethical significance of both a burden-benefit analysis and patient autonomy, the report stated that when a patient or surrogate in collaboration with a responsible healthcare professional decides that a treatment under way and the life it supports have become more burdensome than beneficial to the patient, that is sufficient reason to stop. There is no ethical requirement that treatment, once initiated, must continue against the patient’s wishes or when the surrogate determines that it is more burdensome than beneficial from the patient’s perspective. In fact, imposing treatment in such circumstances violates the patient’s right to self-determination.3

The report noted further that, because of frequent uncertainty about the efficacy of proposed treatments, it is preferable to initiate time-limited trials of treatments and then later stop them if they prove ineffective or become overly burdensome from a patient’s perspective.

ICDs ARE LIKE OTHER LIFE-SUSTAINING THERAPIES

In this issue of Cleveland Clinic Journal of Medicine, Baibars et al4 address the question of how implantable cardioverter-defibrillators (ICDs) should be managed at the end of life. The historical events and developments recounted above regarding withdrawing life-sustaining technologies are an appropriate context for ethically assessing the management of ICDs for dying patients.

ICDs are not ventilators, but like ventilators, they are a life-sustaining therapy

Obviously, ICDs are not ventilators, but like ventilators, they are life-sustaining therapy, as are dialysis machines, blood transfusions, medically supplied nutrition and hydration, ventricular assist devices, and other implantable electronic cardiac devices such as pacemakers. Each of these life-sustaining therapies, depending on a patient’s clinical condition, underlying illness, and comorbidities, can become a death-prolonging technology.

An ethical framework and analysis about whether to continue any life-sustaining therapy, including an ICD, must include an assessment of the benefit-to-burden ratio from the patient’s perspective. Does the therapy enhance or maintain a quality of life acceptable to the patient? Or has it become overly burdensome and does it maintain a quality of life the patient finds (or would find) unacceptable? If the latter is true, and especially in the context of an underlying terminal condition, then shifting the goals of care to focus on comfort is always appropriate and ethically justified. Treatments—including ICDs—that do not contribute to patient comfort should be withdrawn.

TOWARD COMPETENCY IN ETHICAL MANAGEMENT

Baibars et al note that much more needs to be done to enhance competencies, increase proficiencies, and mitigate the moral distress of healthcare professionals caring for dying patients with ICDs and other devices. To help clinicians achieve a personal and professional “comfort zone” for ethically managing patients with ICDs, we recommend that healthcare institutions, medical schools, and nursing schools take the following steps:

Develop comprehensive end-of-life policies, procedures, and protocols that incorporate specific guidance for managing cardiac devices and that have been endorsed by a hospital ethics committee. Such guidance can be informative and educational and can ensure that decisions and resulting actions (including stopping cardiac devices) are ethically supportable.

Provide more palliative care training in medical and nursing schools, residency programs, and continuing education activities so that front-line clinicians can deliver “basic,” “primary” palliative care not requiring specialty palliative medicine. This training, called for in the Institute of Medicine’s 2014 report, Dying in America,5 should include explicit ethics discussions about managing cardiac devices at the end of life.

Provide ongoing training in communication skills needed for all patient-professional encounters. Effectively engaging patients in goals-of-care discussions, especially patients with life-limiting illnesses such as heart failure, cannot be achieved without these skills.

References
  1. Pence G. Comas: Karen Quinlan and Nancy Cruzan. In: Classic Cases in Medical Ethics: Accounts of Cases That Have Shaped Medical Ethics, With Philosophical, Legal, and Historical Backgrounds, 3rd edition. Boston: McGraw-Hill; 2000:29–55.
  2. In the matter of Karen Quinlan, an alleged incompetent. In re Quinlan. 70 N.J. 10, 355 A.2d 647 (1976), cert. denied, 429 U.S. 922 (1976).
  3. Wolf SM. Hastings Center. Guidelines on the Termination of Life-Sustaining Treatment and Care of the Dying: A Report by the Hastings Center. The Hastings Center: Briarcliff Manor, NY; 1987.
  4. Baibars MM, Alraies MC, Kabach A, Pritzker M. Can patients opt to turn off implantable cardioverter-defibrillators near the end of life? Cleve Clin J Med 2016; 83:97–98.
  5. National Academy of Sciences. Dying in America: improving quality and honoring individual p near the end of life. www.iom.edu/Reports/2014/Dying-In-America-Improving-Quality-and-Honoring-Individual-P-Near-the-End-of-Life.aspx. Accessed January 4, 2016.
References
  1. Pence G. Comas: Karen Quinlan and Nancy Cruzan. In: Classic Cases in Medical Ethics: Accounts of Cases That Have Shaped Medical Ethics, With Philosophical, Legal, and Historical Backgrounds, 3rd edition. Boston: McGraw-Hill; 2000:29–55.
  2. In the matter of Karen Quinlan, an alleged incompetent. In re Quinlan. 70 N.J. 10, 355 A.2d 647 (1976), cert. denied, 429 U.S. 922 (1976).
  3. Wolf SM. Hastings Center. Guidelines on the Termination of Life-Sustaining Treatment and Care of the Dying: A Report by the Hastings Center. The Hastings Center: Briarcliff Manor, NY; 1987.
  4. Baibars MM, Alraies MC, Kabach A, Pritzker M. Can patients opt to turn off implantable cardioverter-defibrillators near the end of life? Cleve Clin J Med 2016; 83:97–98.
  5. National Academy of Sciences. Dying in America: improving quality and honoring individual p near the end of life. www.iom.edu/Reports/2014/Dying-In-America-Improving-Quality-and-Honoring-Individual-P-Near-the-End-of-Life.aspx. Accessed January 4, 2016.
Issue
Cleveland Clinic Journal of Medicine - 83(2)
Issue
Cleveland Clinic Journal of Medicine - 83(2)
Page Number
99-100
Page Number
99-100
Publications
Publications
Topics
Article Type
Display Headline
The ethics of ICDs: History and future directions
Display Headline
The ethics of ICDs: History and future directions
Legacy Keywords
implantable cardioverter-defibrillator, ICD, end of life, cardiac implantable electronic device, CIED, withdrawing therapy, Karen Ann Quinlan, Hastings Center, life-sustaining therapy, hospice, Martin Smith, Eric Kodish
Legacy Keywords
implantable cardioverter-defibrillator, ICD, end of life, cardiac implantable electronic device, CIED, withdrawing therapy, Karen Ann Quinlan, Hastings Center, life-sustaining therapy, hospice, Martin Smith, Eric Kodish
Sections
Disallow All Ads
Alternative CME
Article PDF Media

From the summit directors

Article Type
Changed
Tue, 10/02/2018 - 14:31
Display Headline
From the summit directors

Surgical innovation lives on the border between tradition and regulation in a vaguely defined frontier. Over the course of many centuries, a framework for clinical medical ethics has developed with broad consensus regarding fiduciary obligations between patient and doctor, the principles of beneficence and nonmaleficence, and, more recently, respect for persons and autonomy. During the past century, a parallel set of ethical and regulatory norms has developed surrounding the ethics of research involving human subjects. While both sets of frameworks—those governing clinical ethics and those governing research ethics—contribute to understanding the ethical challenges that arise in the course of surgical innovation, neither is alone sufficient to provide clear guidance.

We decided that further discourse would help resolve some of the ambiguity that exists between the frameworks of clinical ethics and research ethics, and we set out to convene a summit meeting to provide a forum for this discourse. It was our hope that bringing together some of the nation’s foremost surgical innovators with leading bioethicists would catalyze a series of presentations and discussions to create a meaningful ethical framework for thinking about surgical innovation. The summit took place May 8–9, 2008, at Cleveland Clinic, and we were not disappointed. We now have the pleasure of presenting the proceedings in text form.

The summit’s five panel presentations and discussions and two keynote addresses shared the objective of educating participants about moral dilemmas that often arise in the conduct of device development and other innovations in surgery. Panelists suggested potential solutions to the challenges of protecting patients from risk without hindering creativity and progress.

The ethical challenges faced by surgical innovators will not go away. As we develop and refine technology, including new devices, procedures, and transplants, new problems will arise. Two examples of complicated issues on the horizon are robotic surgery and natural orifice transluminal endoscopic surgery (NOTES). While the specific developments will change, the ethical basis of our actions should remain constant. We need to always ask the same questions:

  • Is this in the best interests of the patient?
  • Have we been thoughtful and effective in the process of informed consent?
  • Will our actions be consistent with our own professional integrity?

Our hope is that these proceedings will prompt the necessary next steps: further development of these ideas, writing of papers and convening of more meetings, and, most importantly, further innovation to continue helping patients.

Article PDF
Author and Disclosure Information

Eric Kodish, MD
Chairman, Department of Bioethics, Cleveland Clinic; Professor of Pediatrics, Cleveland Clinic Lerner College of Medicine of Case Western Reserve University Cleveland Clinic

Allen Bashour, MD
Department of Cardiothoracic Anesthesiology and Critical Care Center, and Chairman, Ethics Committee, Cleveland Clinic

Publications
Page Number
S1
Author and Disclosure Information

Eric Kodish, MD
Chairman, Department of Bioethics, Cleveland Clinic; Professor of Pediatrics, Cleveland Clinic Lerner College of Medicine of Case Western Reserve University Cleveland Clinic

Allen Bashour, MD
Department of Cardiothoracic Anesthesiology and Critical Care Center, and Chairman, Ethics Committee, Cleveland Clinic

Author and Disclosure Information

Eric Kodish, MD
Chairman, Department of Bioethics, Cleveland Clinic; Professor of Pediatrics, Cleveland Clinic Lerner College of Medicine of Case Western Reserve University Cleveland Clinic

Allen Bashour, MD
Department of Cardiothoracic Anesthesiology and Critical Care Center, and Chairman, Ethics Committee, Cleveland Clinic

Article PDF
Article PDF

Surgical innovation lives on the border between tradition and regulation in a vaguely defined frontier. Over the course of many centuries, a framework for clinical medical ethics has developed with broad consensus regarding fiduciary obligations between patient and doctor, the principles of beneficence and nonmaleficence, and, more recently, respect for persons and autonomy. During the past century, a parallel set of ethical and regulatory norms has developed surrounding the ethics of research involving human subjects. While both sets of frameworks—those governing clinical ethics and those governing research ethics—contribute to understanding the ethical challenges that arise in the course of surgical innovation, neither is alone sufficient to provide clear guidance.

We decided that further discourse would help resolve some of the ambiguity that exists between the frameworks of clinical ethics and research ethics, and we set out to convene a summit meeting to provide a forum for this discourse. It was our hope that bringing together some of the nation’s foremost surgical innovators with leading bioethicists would catalyze a series of presentations and discussions to create a meaningful ethical framework for thinking about surgical innovation. The summit took place May 8–9, 2008, at Cleveland Clinic, and we were not disappointed. We now have the pleasure of presenting the proceedings in text form.

The summit’s five panel presentations and discussions and two keynote addresses shared the objective of educating participants about moral dilemmas that often arise in the conduct of device development and other innovations in surgery. Panelists suggested potential solutions to the challenges of protecting patients from risk without hindering creativity and progress.

The ethical challenges faced by surgical innovators will not go away. As we develop and refine technology, including new devices, procedures, and transplants, new problems will arise. Two examples of complicated issues on the horizon are robotic surgery and natural orifice transluminal endoscopic surgery (NOTES). While the specific developments will change, the ethical basis of our actions should remain constant. We need to always ask the same questions:

  • Is this in the best interests of the patient?
  • Have we been thoughtful and effective in the process of informed consent?
  • Will our actions be consistent with our own professional integrity?

Our hope is that these proceedings will prompt the necessary next steps: further development of these ideas, writing of papers and convening of more meetings, and, most importantly, further innovation to continue helping patients.

Surgical innovation lives on the border between tradition and regulation in a vaguely defined frontier. Over the course of many centuries, a framework for clinical medical ethics has developed with broad consensus regarding fiduciary obligations between patient and doctor, the principles of beneficence and nonmaleficence, and, more recently, respect for persons and autonomy. During the past century, a parallel set of ethical and regulatory norms has developed surrounding the ethics of research involving human subjects. While both sets of frameworks—those governing clinical ethics and those governing research ethics—contribute to understanding the ethical challenges that arise in the course of surgical innovation, neither is alone sufficient to provide clear guidance.

We decided that further discourse would help resolve some of the ambiguity that exists between the frameworks of clinical ethics and research ethics, and we set out to convene a summit meeting to provide a forum for this discourse. It was our hope that bringing together some of the nation’s foremost surgical innovators with leading bioethicists would catalyze a series of presentations and discussions to create a meaningful ethical framework for thinking about surgical innovation. The summit took place May 8–9, 2008, at Cleveland Clinic, and we were not disappointed. We now have the pleasure of presenting the proceedings in text form.

The summit’s five panel presentations and discussions and two keynote addresses shared the objective of educating participants about moral dilemmas that often arise in the conduct of device development and other innovations in surgery. Panelists suggested potential solutions to the challenges of protecting patients from risk without hindering creativity and progress.

The ethical challenges faced by surgical innovators will not go away. As we develop and refine technology, including new devices, procedures, and transplants, new problems will arise. Two examples of complicated issues on the horizon are robotic surgery and natural orifice transluminal endoscopic surgery (NOTES). While the specific developments will change, the ethical basis of our actions should remain constant. We need to always ask the same questions:

  • Is this in the best interests of the patient?
  • Have we been thoughtful and effective in the process of informed consent?
  • Will our actions be consistent with our own professional integrity?

Our hope is that these proceedings will prompt the necessary next steps: further development of these ideas, writing of papers and convening of more meetings, and, most importantly, further innovation to continue helping patients.

Page Number
S1
Page Number
S1
Publications
Publications
Article Type
Display Headline
From the summit directors
Display Headline
From the summit directors
Citation Override
Cleveland Clinic Journal of Medicine 2008 November;75(suppl 6):S1
Disallow All Ads
Content Gating
No Gating (article Unlocked/Free)
Alternative CME
Disqus Comments
Default
Gate On Date
Mon, 06/04/2018 - 13:30
Un-Gate On Date
Mon, 06/04/2018 - 13:30
Use ProPublica
CFC Schedule Remove Status
Mon, 06/04/2018 - 13:30
Article PDF Media